<SPAN name="startofbook"></SPAN>
<h1>SIGNS OF CHANGE</h1>
<p style="text-align: center"><b>Seven Lectures</b></p>
<p style="text-align: center"><span class="GutSmall"><i>DELIVERED
ON VARIOUS OCCASIONS</i></span></p>
<div class="gapspace"> </div>
<p style="text-align: center"><span class="GutSmall">BY</span></p>
<p style="text-align: center">WILLIAM MORRIS<br/>
<span class="GutSmall">AUTHOR OF “THE EARTHLY
PARADISE”</span></p>
<div class="gapspace"> </div>
<p style="text-align: center">LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO.<br/>
<span class="GutSmall">LONDON, NEW YORK, AND BOMBAY</span><br/>
<span class="GutSmall">1896</span></p>
<p style="text-align: center"><span class="GutSmall"><i>All
rights reserved</i></span></p>
<h2>CONTENTS.</h2>
<table>
<tr>
<td><p> </p>
</td>
<td><p style="text-align: right"><span class="GutSmall">PAGE</span></p>
</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p><span class="smcap">How we Live and How we Might
Live</span></p>
</td>
<td><p style="text-align: right"><span class="indexpageno"><SPAN href="#page1">1</SPAN></span></p>
</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p><span class="smcap">Whigs, Democrats, and
Socialists</span></p>
</td>
<td><p style="text-align: right"><span class="indexpageno"><SPAN href="#page37">37</SPAN></span></p>
</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p><span class="smcap">Feudal England</span></p>
</td>
<td><p style="text-align: right"><span class="indexpageno"><SPAN href="#page55">55</SPAN></span></p>
</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p><span class="smcap">The Hopes of Civilization</span></p>
</td>
<td><p style="text-align: right"><span class="indexpageno"><SPAN href="#page84">84</SPAN></span></p>
</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p><span class="smcap">The Aims of Art</span></p>
</td>
<td><p style="text-align: right"><span class="indexpageno"><SPAN href="#page117">117</SPAN></span></p>
</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p><span class="smcap">Useful Work </span><span class="smcap"><i>versus</i></span><span class="smcap"> Useless
Toil</span></p>
</td>
<td><p style="text-align: right"><span class="indexpageno"><SPAN href="#page141">141</SPAN></span></p>
</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p><span class="smcap">Dawn of a New Epoch</span></p>
</td>
<td><p style="text-align: right"><span class="indexpageno"><SPAN href="#page174">174</SPAN></span></p>
</td>
</tr>
</table>
<h2><SPAN name="page1"></SPAN><span class="pagenum"></span>HOW WE LIVE AND HOW WE MIGHT LIVE.</h2>
<p><span class="smcap">The</span> word Revolution, which we
Socialists are so often forced to use, has a terrible sound in
most people’s ears, even when we have explained to them
that it does not necessarily mean a change accompanied by riot
and all kinds of violence, and cannot mean a change made
mechanically and in the teeth of opinion by a group of men who
have somehow managed to seize on the executive power for the
moment. Even when we explain that we use the word
revolution in its etymological sense, and mean by it a change in
the basis of society, people are scared at the idea of such a
vast change, and beg that you will speak of reform and not
revolution. As, however, we Socialists do not at all mean
by our word revolution what these worthy people mean by their
word reform, I can’t help thinking that it would be a
mistake to use it, whatever projects we might conceal beneath its
harmless envelope. So we will stick to our word, which
means a change of the basis of society; it may frighten people,
but it will at least warn them that there is something to be
frightened about, which will be no less dangerous for being
ignored; and also it may encourage some people, and will mean to
them at least not a fear, but a hope.</p>
<p>Fear and Hope—those are the names of the two great
passions which rule the race of man, and with which
revolutionists have to deal; to give hope to the many oppressed
and fear to the few oppressors, that is our business; if we do
the first and give hope to the many, the few <i>must</i> be
frightened by their hope; otherwise we do not want to frighten
them; it is not revenge we want for poor people, but happiness;
indeed, what revenge can be taken for all the thousands of years
of the sufferings of the poor?</p>
<p>However, many of the oppressors of the poor, most of them, we
will say, are not conscious of their being oppressors (we shall
see why presently); they live in an orderly, quiet way
themselves, as far as possible removed from the feelings of a
Roman slave-owner or a Legree; they know that the poor exist, but
their sufferings do not present themselves to them in a trenchant
and dramatic way; they themselves have troubles to bear, and they
think doubtless that to bear trouble is the lot of humanity, nor
have they any means of comparing the troubles of their lives with
those of people lower in the social scale; and if ever the
thought of those heavier troubles obtrudes itself upon them, they
console themselves with the maxim that people do get used to the
troubles they have to bear, whatever they may be.</p>
<p>Indeed, as far as regards individuals at least, that is but
too true, so that we have as supporters of the present state of
things, however bad it may be, first those comfortable
unconscious oppressors who think that they have everything to
fear from any change which would involve more than the softest
and most gradual of reforms, and secondly those poor people who,
living hard and anxiously as they do, can hardly conceive of any
change for the better happening to them, and dare not risk one
tittle of their poor possessions in taking any action towards a
possible bettering of their condition; so that while we can do
little with the rich save inspire them with fear, it is hard
indeed to give the poor any hope. It is, then, no less than
reasonable that those whom we try to involve in the great
struggle for a better form of life than that which we now lead
should call on us to give them at least some idea of what that
life may be like.</p>
<p>A reasonable request, but hard to satisfy, since we are living
under a system that makes conscious effort towards reconstruction
almost impossible: it is not unreasonable on our part to answer,
“There are certain definite obstacles to the real progress
of man; we can tell you what these are; take them away, and then
you shall see.”</p>
<p>However, I purpose now to offer myself as a victim for the
satisfaction of those who consider that as things now go we have
at least got something, and are terrified at the idea of losing
their hold of that, lest they should find they are worse off than
before, and have nothing. Yet in the course of my endeavour
to show how we might live, I must more or less deal in
negatives. I mean to say I must point out where in my
opinion we fall short in our present attempts at decent
life. I must ask the rich and well-to-do what sort of a
position it is which they are so anxious to preserve at any cost?
and if, after all, it will be such a terrible loss to them to
give it up? and I must point out to the poor that they, with
capacities for living a dignified and generous life, are in a
position which they cannot endure without continued
degradation.</p>
<p>How do we live, then, under our present system? Let us
look at it a little.</p>
<p>And first, please to understand that our present system of
Society is based on a state of perpetual war. Do any of you
think that this is as it should be? I know that you have
often been told that the competition, which is at present the
rule of all production, is a good thing, and stimulates the
progress of the race; but the people who tell you this should
call competition by its shorter name of <i>war</i> if they wish
to be honest, and you would then be free to consider whether or
no war stimulates progress, otherwise than as a mad bull chasing
you over your own garden may do. War or competition,
whichever you please to call it, means at the best pursuing your
own advantage at the cost of some one else’s loss, and in
the process of it you must not be sparing of destruction even of
your own possessions, or you will certainly come by the worse in
the struggle. You understand that perfectly as to the kind
of war in which people go out to kill and be killed; that sort of
war in which ships are commissioned, for instance, “to
sink, burn, and destroy;” but it appears that you are not
so conscious of this waste of goods when you are only carrying on
that other war called <i>commerce</i>; observe, however, that the
waste is there all the same.</p>
<p>Now let us look at this kind of war a little closer, run
through some of the forms of it, that we may see how the
“burn, sink, and destroy” is carried on in it.</p>
<p>First, you have that form of it called national rivalry, which
in good truth is nowadays the cause of all gunpowder and bayonet
wars which civilized nations wage. For years past we
English have been rather shy of them, except on those happy
occasions when we could carry them on at no sort of risk to
ourselves, when the killing was all on one side, or at all events
when we hoped it would be. We have been shy of gunpowder
war with a respectable enemy for a long while, and I will tell
you why: It is because we have had the lion’s-share of the
world-market; we didn’t want to fight for it as a nation,
for we had got it; but now this is changing in a most
significant, and, to a Socialist, a most cheering way; we are
losing or have lost that lion’s share; it is now a
desperate “competition” between the great nations of
civilization for the world-market, and to-morrow it may be a
desperate war for that end. As a result, the furthering of
war (if it be not on too large a scale) is no longer confined to
the honour-and-glory kind of old Tories, who if they meant
anything at all by it meant that a Tory war would be a good
occasion for damping down democracy; we have changed all that,
and now it is quite another kind of politician that is wont to
urge us on to “patriotism” as ’tis
called. The leaders of the Progressive Liberals, as they
would call themselves, long-headed persons who know well enough
that social movements are going on, who are not blind to the fact
that the world will move with their help or without it; these
have been the Jingoes of these later days. I don’t
mean to say they know what they are doing: politicians, as you
well know, take good care to shut their eyes to everything that
may happen six months ahead; but what is being done is this: that
the present system, which always must include national rivalry,
is pushing us into a desperate scramble for the markets on more
or less equal terms with other nations, because, once more, we
have lost that command of them which we once had. Desperate
is not too strong a word. We shall let this impulse to
snatch markets carry us whither it will, whither it must.
To-day it is successful burglary and disgrace, to-morrow it may
be mere defeat and disgrace.</p>
<p>Now this is not a digression, although in saying this I am
nearer to what is generally called politics than I shall be
again. I only want to show you what commercial war comes to
when it has to do with foreign nations, and that even the dullest
can see how mere waste must go with it. That is how we live
now with foreign nations, prepared to ruin them without war if
possible, with it if necessary, let alone meantime the
disgraceful exploiting of savage tribes and barbarous peoples, on
whom we force at once our shoddy wares and our hypocrisy at the
cannon’s mouth.</p>
<p>Well, surely Socialism can offer you something in the place of
all that. It can; it can offer you peace and friendship
instead of war. We might live utterly without national
rivalries, acknowledging that while it is best for those who feel
that they naturally form a community under one name to govern
themselves, yet that no community in civilization should feel
that it had interests opposed any other, their economical
condition being at any rate similar; so that any citizen of one
community could fall to work and live without disturbance of his
life when he was in a foreign country, and would fit into his
place quite naturally; so that all civilized nations would form
one great community, agreeing together as to the kind and amount
of production and distribution needed; working at such and such
production where it could be best produced; avoiding waste by all
means. Please to think of the amount of waste which they
would avoid, how much such a revolution would add to the wealth
of the world! What creature on earth would be harmed by
such a revolution? Nay, would not everybody be the better
for it? And what hinders it? I will tell you
presently.</p>
<p>Meantime let us pass from this “competition”
between nations to that between “the organizers of
labour,” great firms, joint-stock companies; capitalists in
short, and see how competition “stimulates
production” among them: indeed it does do that; but what
kind of production? Well, production of something to sell
at a profit, or say production of profits: and note how war
commercial stimulates that: a certain market is demanding goods;
there are, say, a hundred manufacturers who make that kind of
goods, and every one of them would if he could keep that market
to himself; and struggles desperately to get as much of it as he
can, with the obvious result that presently the thing is
overdone, and the market is glutted, and all that fury of
manufacture has to sink into cold ashes. Doesn’t that
seem something like war to you? Can’t you see the
waste of it—waste of labour, skill, cunning, waste of life
in short? Well, you may say, but it cheapens the
goods. In a sense it does; and yet only apparently, as
wages have a tendency to sink for the ordinary worker in
proportion as prices sink; and at what a cost do we gain this
appearance of cheapness! Plainly speaking, at the cost of
cheating the consumer and starving the real producer for the
benefit of the gambler, who uses both consumer and producer as
his milch cows. I needn’t go at length into the
subject of adulteration, for every one knows what kind of a part
it plays in this sort of commerce; but remember that it is an
absolutely necessary incident to the production of profit out of
wares, which is the business of the so-called manufacturer; and
this you must understand, that, taking him in the lump, the
consumer is perfectly helpless against the gambler; the goods are
forced on him by their cheapness, and with them a certain kind of
life which that energetic, that aggressive cheapness determines
for him: for so far-reaching is this curse of commercial war that
no country is safe from its ravages; the traditions of a thousand
years fall before it in a month; it overruns a weak or
semi-barbarous country, and whatever romance or pleasure or art
existed there, is trodden down into a mire of sordidness and
ugliness; the Indian or Javanese craftsman may no longer ply his
craft leisurely, working a few hours a day, in producing a maze
of strange beauty on a piece of cloth: a steam-engine is set
a-going at Manchester, and that victory over nature and a
thousand stubborn difficulties is used for the base work of
producing a sort of plaster of china-clay and shoddy, and the
Asiatic worker, if he is not starved to death outright, as
plentifully happens, is driven himself into a factory to lower
the wages of his Manchester brother worker, and nothing of
character is left him except, most like, an accumulation of fear
and hatred of that to him most unaccountable evil, his English
master. The South Sea Islander must leave his
canoe-carving, his sweet rest, and his graceful dances, and
become the slave of a slave: trousers, shoddy, rum, missionary,
and fatal disease—he must swallow all this civilization in
the lump, and neither himself nor we can help him now till social
order displaces the hideous tyranny of gambling that has ruined
him.</p>
<p>Let those be types of the consumer: but now for the producer;
I mean the real producer, the worker; how does this scramble for
the plunder of the market affect him? The manufacturer, in
the eagerness of his war, has had to collect into one
neighbourhood a vast army of workers, he has drilled them till
they are as fit as may be for his special branch of production,
that is, for making a profit out of it, and with the result of
their being fit for nothing else: well, when the glut comes in
that market he is supplying, what happens to this army, every
private in which has been depending on the steady demand in that
market, and acting, as he could not choose but act, as if it were
to go on for ever? You know well what happens to these men:
the factory door is shut on them; on a very large part of them
often, and at the best on the reserve army of labour, so busily
employed in the time of inflation. What becomes of
them? Nay, we know that well enough just now. But
what we don’t know, or don’t choose to know, is, that
this reserve army of labour is an absolute necessity for
commercial war; if <i>our</i> manufacturers had not got these
poor devils whom they could draft on to their machines when the
demand swelled, other manufacturers in France, or Germany, or
America, would step in and take the market from them.</p>
<p>So you see, as we live now, it is necessary that a vast part
of the industrial population should be exposed to the danger of
periodical semi-starvation, and that, not for the advantage of
the people in another part of the world, but for their
degradation and enslavement.</p>
<p>Just let your minds run for a moment on the kind of waste
which this means, this opening up of new markets among savage and
barbarous countries which is the extreme type of the force of the
profit-market on the world, and you will surely see what a
hideous nightmare that profit-market is: it keeps us sweating and
terrified for our livelihood, unable to read a book, or look at a
picture, or have pleasant fields to walk in, or to lie in the
sun, or to share in the knowledge of our time, to have in short
either animal or intellectual pleasure, and for what? that we may
go on living the same slavish life till we die, in order to
provide for a rich man what is called a life of ease and luxury;
that is to say, a life so empty, unwholesome, and degraded, that
perhaps, on the whole, he is worse off than we the workers are:
and as to the result of all this suffering, it is luckiest when
it is nothing at all, when you can say that the wares have done
nobody any good; for oftenest they have done many people harm,
and we have toiled and groaned and died in making poison and
destruction for our fellow-men.</p>
<p>Well, I say all this is war, and the results of war, the war
this time, not of competing nations, but of competing firms or
capitalist units: and it is this war of the firms which hinders
the peace between nations which you surely have agreed with me in
thinking is so necessary; for you must know that war is the very
breath of the nostrils of these fighting firms, and they have
now, in our times, got into their hands nearly all the political
power, and they band together in each country in order to make
their respective governments fulfil just two functions: the first
is at home to act as a strong police force, to keep the ring in
which the strong are beating down the weak; the second is to act
as a piratical body-guard abroad, a petard to explode the doors
which lead to the markets of the world: markets at any price
abroad, uninterfered-with privilege, falsely called
<i>laissez-faire</i>, <SPAN name="citation13"></SPAN><SPAN href="#footnote13" class="citation">[13]</SPAN> at any price at
home, to provide these is the sole business of a government such
as our industrial captains have been able to conceive of. I
must now try to show you the reason of all this, and what it
rests on, by trying to answer the question, Why have the
profit-makers got all this power, or at least why are they able
to keep it?</p>
<p>That takes us to the third form of war commercial: the last,
and, the one which all the rest is founded on. We have
spoken first of the war of rival nations; next of that of rival
firms: we have now to speak of rival men. As nations under
the present system are driven to compete with one another for the
markets of the world, and as firms or the captains of industry
have to scramble for their share of the profits of the markets,
so also have the workers to compete with each other—for
livelihood; and it is this constant competition or war amongst
them which enables the profit-grinders to make their profits, and
by means of the wealth so acquired to take all the executive
power of the country into their hands. But here is the
difference between the position of the workers and the
profit-makers: to the latter, the profit-grinders, war is
necessary; you cannot have profit-making without competition,
individual, corporate, and national; but you may work for a
livelihood without competing; you may combine instead of
competing.</p>
<p>I have said war was the life-breath of the profit-makers; in
like manner, combination is the life of the workers. The
working-classes or proletariat cannot even exist as a class
without combination of some sort. The necessity which
forced the profit-grinders to collect their men first into
workshops working by the division of labour, and next into great
factories worked by machinery, and so gradually to draw them into
the great towns and centres of civilization, gave birth to a
distinct working-class or proletariat: and this it was which gave
them their <i>mechanical</i> existence, so to say. But
note, that they are indeed combined into social groups for the
production of wares, but only as yet mechanically; they do not
know what they are working at, nor whom they are working for,
because they are combining to produce wares of which the profit
of a master forms an essential part, instead of goods for their
own use: as long as they do this, and compete with each other for
leave to do it, they will be, and will feel themselves to be,
simply a part of those competing firms I have been speaking of;
they will be in fact just a part of the machinery for the
production of profit; and so long as this lasts it will be the
aim of the masters or profit-makers to decrease the market value
of this human part of the machinery; that is to say, since they
already hold in their hands the labour of dead men in the form of
capital and machinery, it is their interest, or we will say their
necessity, to pay as little as they can help for the labour of
living men which they have to buy from day to day: and since the
workmen they employ have nothing but their labour-power, they are
compelled to underbid one another for employment and wages, and
so enable the capitalist to play his game.</p>
<p>I have said that, as things go, the workers are a part of the
competing firms, an adjunct of capital. Nevertheless, they
are only so by compulsion; and, even without their being
conscious of it, they struggle against that compulsion and its
immediate results, the lowering of their wages, of their standard
of life; and this they do, and must do, both as a class and
individually: just as the slave of the great Roman lord, though
he distinctly felt himself to be a part of the household, yet
collectively was a force in reserve for its destruction, and
individually stole from his lord whenever he could safely do
so. So, here, you see, is another form of war necessary to
the way we live now, the war of class against class, which, when
it rises to its height, and it seems to be rising at present,
will destroy those other forms of war we have been speaking of;
will make the position of the profit-makers, of perpetual
commercial war, untenable; will destroy the present system of
competitive privilege, or commercial war.</p>
<p>Now observe, I said that to the existence of the workers it
was combination, not competition, that was necessary, while to
that of the profit-makers combination was impossible, and war
necessary. The present position of the workers is that of
the machinery of commerce, or in plainer words its slaves; when
they change that position and become free, the class of
profit-makers must cease to exist; and what will then be the
position of the workers? Even as it is they are the one
necessary part of society, the life-giving part; the other
classes are but hangers-on who live on them. But what
should they be, what will they be, when they, once for all, come
to know their real power, and cease competing with one another
for livelihood? I will tell you: they will be society, they
will be the community. And being society—that is,
there being no class outside them to contend with—they can
then regulate their labour in accordance with their own real
needs.</p>
<p>There is much talk about supply and demand, but the supply and
demand usually meant is an artificial one; it is under the sway
of the gambling market; the demand is forced, as I hinted above,
before it is supplied; nor, as each producer is working against
all the rest, can the producers hold their hands, till the market
is glutted and the workers, thrown out on the streets, hear that
there has been over-production, amidst which over-plus of
unsaleable goods they go ill-supplied with even necessaries,
because the wealth which they themselves have created is
“ill-distributed,” as we call it—that is,
unjustly taken away from them.</p>
<p>When the workers are society they will regulate their labour,
so that the supply and demand shall be genuine, not gambling; the
two will then be commensurate, for it is the same society which
demands that also supplies; there will be no more artificial
famines then, no more poverty amidst over-production, amidst too
great a stock of the very things which should supply poverty and
turn it into well-being. In short, there will be no waste
and therefore no tyranny.</p>
<p>Well, now, what Socialism offers you in place of these
artificial famines, with their so-called over-production, is,
once more, regulation of the markets; supply and demand
commensurate; no gambling, and consequently (once more) no waste;
not overwork and weariness for the worker one month, and the next
no work and terror of starvation, but steady work and plenty of
leisure every month; not cheap market wares, that is to say,
adulterated wares, with scarcely any <i>good</i> in them, mere
scaffold-poles for building up profits; no labour would be spent
on such things as these, which people would cease to want when
they ceased to be slaves. Not these, but such goods as best
fulfilled the real uses of the consumers, would labour be set to
make; for profit being abolished, people could have what they
wanted, instead of what the profit-grinders at home and abroad
forced them to take.</p>
<p>For what I want you to understand is this: that in every
civilized country at least there is plenty for all—is, or
at any rate might be. Even with labour so misdirected as it
is at present, an equitable distribution of the wealth we have
would make all people comparatively comfortable; but that is
nothing to the wealth we might have if labour were not
misdirected.</p>
<p>Observe, in the early days of the history of man he was the
slave of his most immediate necessities; Nature was mighty and he
was feeble, and he had to wage constant war with her for his
daily food and such shelter as he could get. His life was
bound down and limited by this constant struggle; all his morals,
laws, religion, are in fact the outcome and the reflection of
this ceaseless toil of earning his livelihood. Time passed,
and little by little, step by step, he grew stronger, till now
after all these ages he has almost completely conquered Nature,
and one would think should now have leisure to turn his thoughts
towards higher things than procuring to-morrow’s
dinner. But, alas! his progress has been broken and
halting; and though he has indeed conquered Nature and has her
forces under his control to do what he will with, he still has
himself to conquer, he still has to think how he will best use
those forces which he has mastered. At present he uses them
blindly, foolishly, as one driven by mere fate. It would
almost seem as if some phantom of the ceaseless pursuit of food
which was once the master of the savage was still hunting the
civilized man; who toils in a dream, as it were, haunted by mere
dim unreal hopes, borne of vague recollections of the days gone
by. Out of that dream he must wake, and face things as they
really are. The conquest of Nature is complete, may we not
say? and now our business is, and has for long been, the
organization of man, who wields the forces of Nature. Nor
till this is attempted at least shall we ever be free of that
terrible phantom of fear of starvation which, with its brother
devil, desire of domination, drives us into injustice, cruelty,
and dastardliness of all kinds: to cease to fear our fellows and
learn to depend on them, to do away with competition and build up
co-operation, is our one necessity.</p>
<p>Now, to get closer to details; you probably know that every
man in civilization is worth, so to say, more than his skin;
working, as he must work, socially, he can produce more than will
keep himself alive and in fair condition; and this has been so
for many centuries, from the time, in fact, when warring tribes
began to make their conquered enemies slaves instead of killing
them; and of course his capacity of producing these extras has
gone on increasing faster and faster, till to-day one man will
weave, for instance, as much cloth in a week as will clothe a
whole village for years: and the real question of civilization
has always been what are we to do with this extra produce of
labour—a question which the phantom, fear of starvation,
and its fellow, desire of domination, has driven men to answer
pretty badly always, and worst of all perhaps in these present
days, when the extra produce has grown with such prodigious
speed. The practical answer has always been for man to
struggle with his fellow for private possession of undue shares
of these extras, and all kinds of devices have been employed by
those who found themselves in possession of the power of taking
them from others to keep those whom they had robbed in perpetual
subjection; and these latter, as I have already hinted, had no
chance of resisting this fleecing as long as they were few and
scattered, and consequently could have little sense of their
common oppression. But now that, owing to the very pursuit
of these undue shares of profit, or extra earnings, men have
become more dependent on each other for production, and have been
driven, as I said before, to combine together for that end more
completely, the power of the workers—that is to say, of the
robbed or fleeced class—has enormously increased, and it
only remains for them to understand that they have this
power. When they do that they will be able to give the
right answer to the question what is to be done with the extra
products of labour over and above what will keep the labourer
alive to labour: which answer is, that the worker will have all
that he produces, and not be fleeced at all: and remember that he
produces collectively, and therefore he will do effectively what
work is required of him according to his capacity, and of the
produce of that work he will have what he needs; because, you
see, he cannot <i>use</i> more than he needs—he can only
<i>waste</i> it.</p>
<p>If this arrangement seems to you preposterously ideal, as it
well may, looking at our present condition, I must back it up by
saying that when men are organized so that their labour is not
wasted, they will be relieved from the fear of starvation and the
desire of domination, and will have freedom and leisure to look
round and see what they really do need.</p>
<p>Now something of that I can conceive for my own self, and I
will lay my ideas before you, so that you may compare them with
your own, asking you always to remember that the very differences
in men’s capacities and desires, after the common need of
food and shelter is satisfied, will make it easier to deal with
their desires in a communal state of things.</p>
<p>What is it that I need, therefore, which my surrounding
circumstances can give me—my dealings with my
fellow-men—setting aside inevitable accidents which
co-operation and forethought cannot control, if there be
such?</p>
<p>Well, first of all I claim good health; and I say that a vast
proportion of people in civilization scarcely even know what that
means. To feel mere life a pleasure; to enjoy the moving
one’s limbs and exercising one’s bodily powers; to
play, as it were, with sun and wind and rain; to rejoice in
satisfying the due bodily appetites of a human animal without
fear of degradation or sense of wrong-doing: yes, and therewithal
to be well formed, straight-limbed, strongly knit, expressive of
countenance—to be, in a word, beautiful—that also I
claim. If we cannot have this claim satisfied, we are but
poor creatures after all; and I claim it in the teeth of those
terrible doctrines of asceticism, which, born of the despair of
the oppressed and degraded, have been for so many ages used as
instruments for the continuance of that oppression and
degradation.</p>
<p>And I believe that this claim for a healthy body for all of us
carries with it all other due claims: for who knows where the
seeds of disease which even rich people suffer from were first
sown: from the luxury of an ancestor, perhaps; yet often, I
suspect, from his poverty. And for the poor: a
distinguished physicist has said that the poor suffer always from
one disease—hunger; and at least I know this, that if a man
is overworked in any degree he cannot enjoy the sort of health I
am speaking of; nor can he if he is continually chained to one
dull round of mechanical work, with no hope at the other end of
it; nor if he lives in continual sordid anxiety for his
livelihood, nor if he is ill-housed, nor if he is deprived of all
enjoyment of the natural beauty of the world, nor if he has no
amusement to quicken the flow of his spirits from time to time:
all these things, which touch more or less directly on his bodily
condition, are born of the claim I make to live in good health;
indeed, I suspect that these good conditions must have been in
force for several generations before a population in general will
be really healthy, as I have hinted above; but also I doubt not
that in the course of time they would, joined to other
conditions, of which more hereafter, gradually breed such a
population, living in enjoyment of animal life at least, happy
therefore, and beautiful according to the beauty of their
race. On this point I may note that the very variations in
the races of men are caused by the conditions under which they
live, and though in these rougher parts of the world we lack some
of the advantages of climate and surroundings, yet, if we were
working for livelihood and not for profit, we might easily
neutralize many of the disadvantages of our climate, at least
enough give due scope to the full development of our race.</p>
<p>Now the next thing I claim is education. And you must
not say that every English child is educated now; that sort of
education will not answer my claim, though I cheerfully admit it
is something: something, and yet after all only class
education. What I claim is liberal education; opportunity,
that is, to have my share of whatever knowledge there is in the
world according to my capacity or bent of mind, historical or
scientific; and also to have my share of skill of hand which is
about in the world, either in the industrial handicrafts or in
the fine arts; picture-painting, sculpture, music, acting, or the
like: I claim to be taught, if I can be taught, more than one
craft to exercise for the benefit of the community. You may
think this a large claim, but I am clear it is not too large a
claim if the community is to have any gain out of my special
capacities, if we are not all to be beaten down to a dull level
of mediocrity as we are now, all but the very strongest and
toughest of us.</p>
<p>But also I know that this claim for education involves one for
public advantages in the shape of public libraries, schools, and
the like, such as no private person, not even the richest, could
command: but these I claim very confidently, being sure that no
reasonable community could bear to be without such helps to a
decent life.</p>
<p>Again, the claim for education involves a claim for abundant
leisure, which once more I make with confidence; because when
once we have shaken off the slavery of profit, labour would be
organized so unwastefully that no heavy burden would be laid on
the individual citizens; every one of whom as a matter of course
would have to pay his toll of some obviously useful work.
At present you must note that all the amazing machinery which we
have invented has served only to increase the amount of
profit-bearing wares; in other words, to increase the amount of
profit pouched by individuals for their own advantage, part of
which profit they use as capital for the production of more
profit, with ever the same waste attached to it; and part as
private riches or means for luxurious living, which again is
sheer waste—is in fact to be looked on as a kind of bonfire
on which rich men burn up the product of the labour they have
fleeced from the workers beyond what they themselves can
use. So I say that, in spite of our inventions, no worker
works under the present system an hour the less on account of
those labour-saving machines, so-called. But under a
happier state of things they would be used simply for saving
labour, with the result of a vast amount of leisure gained for
the community to be added to that gained by the avoidance of the
waste of useless luxury, and the abolition of the service of
commercial war.</p>
<p>And I may say that as to that leisure, as I should in no case
do any harm to any one with it, so I should often do some direct
good to the community with it, by practising arts or occupations
for my hands or brain which would give pleasure to many of the
citizens; in other words, a great deal of the best work done
would be done in the leisure time of men relieved from any
anxiety as to their livelihood, and eager to exercise their
special talent, as all men, nay, all animals are.</p>
<p>Now, again, this leisure would enable me to please myself and
expand my mind by travelling if I had a mind to it: because, say,
for instance, that I were a shoemaker; if due social order were
established, it by no means follows that I should always be
obliged to make shoes in one place; a due amount of easily
conceivable arrangement would enable me to make shoes in Rome,
say, for three months, and to come back with new ideas of
building, gathered from the sight of the works of past ages,
amongst other things which would perhaps be of service in
London.</p>
<p>But now, in order that my leisure might not degenerate into
idleness and aimlessness, I must set up a claim for due work to
do. Nothing to my mind is more important than this demand,
and I must ask your leave to say something about it. I have
mentioned that I should probably use my leisure for doing a good
deal of what is now called work; but it is clear that if I am a
member of a Socialist Community I must do my due share of rougher
work than this—my due share of what my capacity enables me
to do, that is; no fitting of me to a Procrustean bed; but even
that share of work necessary to the existence of the simplest
social life must, in the first place, whatever else it is, be
reasonable work; that is, it must be such work as a good citizen
can see the necessity for; as a member of the community, I must
have agreed to do it.</p>
<p>To take two strong instances of the contrary, I won’t
submit to be dressed up in red and marched off to shoot at my
French or German or Arab friend in a quarrel that I don’t
understand; I will rebel sooner than do that.</p>
<p>Nor will I submit to waste my time and energies in making some
trifling toy which I know only a fool can desire; I will rebel
sooner than do that.</p>
<p>However, you may be sure that in a state of social order I
shall have no need to rebel against any such pieces of unreason;
only I am forced to speak from the way we live to the way we
might live.</p>
<p>Again, if the necessary reasonable work be of a mechanical
kind, I must be helped to do it by a machine, not to cheapen my
labour, but so that as little time as possible may be spent upon
it, and that I may be able to think of other things while am
tending the machine. And if the work be specially rough or
exhausting, you will, I am sure, agree with me in saying that I
must take turns in doing it with other people; I mean I
mustn’t, for instance, be expected to spend my working
hours always at the bottom of a coal-pit. I think such work
as that ought to be largely volunteer work, and done, as I say,
in spells. And what I say of very rough work I say also of
nasty work. On the other hand, I should think very little
of the manhood of a stout and healthy man who did not feel a
pleasure in doing rough work; always supposing him to work under
the conditions I have been speaking of—namely, feeling that
it was useful (and consequently honoured), and that it was not
continuous or hopeless, and that he was really doing it of his
own free will.</p>
<p>The last claim I make for my work is that the places I worked
in, factories or workshops, should be pleasant, just as the
fields where our most necessary work is done are pleasant.
Believe me there is nothing in the world to prevent this being
done, save the necessity of making profits on all wares; in other
words, the wares are cheapened at the expense of people being
forced to work in crowded, unwholesome, squalid, noisy dens: that
is to say, they are cheapened at the expense of the
workman’s life.</p>
<p>Well, so much for my claims as to my <i>necessary</i> work, my
tribute to the community. I believe people would find, as
they advanced in their capacity for carrying on social order,
that life so lived was much less expensive than we now can have
any idea of; and that, after a little, people would rather be
anxious to seek work than to avoid it; that our working hours
would rather be merry parties of men and maids, young men and old
enjoying themselves over their work, than the grumpy weariness it
mostly is now. Then would come the time for the new birth
of art, so much talked of, so long deferred; people could not
help showing their mirth and pleasure in their work, and would be
always wishing to express it in a tangible and more or less
enduring form, and the workshop would once more be a school of
art, whose influence no one could escape from.</p>
<p>And, again, that word art leads me to my last claim, which is
that the material surroundings of my life should be pleasant,
generous, and beautiful; that I know is a large claim, but this I
will say about it, that if it cannot be satisfied, if every
civilized community cannot provide such surroundings for all its
members, I do not want the world to go on; it is a mere misery
that man has ever existed. I do not think it possible under
the present circumstances to speak too strongly on this
point. I feel sure that the time will come when people will
find it difficult to believe that a rich community such as ours,
having such command over external Nature, could have submitted to
live such a mean, shabby, dirty life as we do.</p>
<p>And once for all, there is nothing in our circumstances save
the hunting of profit that drives us into it. It is profit
which draws men into enormous unmanageable aggregations called
towns, for instance; profit which crowds them up when they are
there into quarters without gardens or open spaces; profit which
won’t take the most ordinary precautions against wrapping a
whole district in a cloud of sulphurous smoke; which turns
beautiful rivers into filthy sewers; which condemns all but the
rich to live in houses idiotically cramped and confined at the
best, and at the worst in houses for whose wretchedness there is
no name.</p>
<p>I say it is almost incredible that we should bear such crass
stupidity as this; nor should we if we could help it. We
shall not bear it when the workers get out of their heads that
they are but an appendage to profit-grinding, that the more
profits that are made the more employment at high wages there
will be for them, and that therefore all the incredible filth,
disorder, and degradation of modern civilization are signs of
their prosperity. So far from that, they are signs of their
slavery. When they are no longer slaves they will claim as
a matter of course that every man and every family should be
generously lodged; that every child should be able to play in a
garden close to the place his parents live in; that the houses
should by their obvious decency and order be ornaments to Nature,
not disfigurements of it; for the decency and order
above-mentioned when carried to the due pitch would most
assuredly lead to beauty in building. All this, of course,
would mean the people—that is, all society—duly
organized, having in its own hands the means of production, to be
<i>owned</i> by no individual, but used by all as occasion called
for its use, and can only be done on those terms; on any other
terms people will be driven to accumulate private wealth for
themselves, and thus, as we have seen, to waste the goods of the
community and perpetuate the division into classes, which means
continual war and waste.</p>
<p>As to what extent it may be necessary or desirable for people
under social order to live in common, we may differ pretty much
according to our tendencies towards social life. For my
part I can’t see why we should think it a hardship to eat
with the people we work with; I am sure that as to many things,
such as valuable books, pictures, and splendour of surroundings,
we shall find it better to club our means together; and I must
say that often when I have been sickened by the stupidity of the
mean idiotic rabbit warrens that rich men build for themselves in
Bayswater and elsewhere, I console myself with visions of the
noble communal hall of the future, unsparing of materials,
generous in worthy ornament, alive with the noblest thoughts of
our time, and the past, embodied in the best art which a free and
manly people could produce; such an abode of man as no private
enterprise could come anywhere near for beauty and fitness,
because only collective thought and collective life could cherish
the aspirations which would give birth to its beauty, or have the
skill and leisure to carry them out. I for my part should
think it much the reverse of a hardship if I had to read my books
and meet my friends in such a place; nor do I think I am better
off to live in a vulgar stuccoed house crowded with upholstery
that I despise, in all respects degrading to the mind and
enervating to the body to live in, simply because I call it my
own, or my house.</p>
<p>It is not an original remark, but I make it here, that my home
is where I meet people with whom I sympathise, whom I love.</p>
<p>Well, that is my opinion as a middle-class man. Whether
a working-class man would think his family possession of his
wretched little room better than his share of the palace of which
I have spoken, I must leave to his opinion, and to the
imaginations of the middle class, who perhaps may sometimes
conceive the fact that the said worker is cramped for space and
comfort—say on washing-day.</p>
<p>Before I leave this matter of the surroundings of life, I wish
to meet a possible objection. I have spoken of machinery
being used freely for releasing people from the more mechanical
and repulsive part of necessary labour; and I know that to some
cultivated people, people of the artistic turn of mind, machinery
is particularly distasteful, and they will be apt to say you will
never get your surroundings pleasant so long as you are
surrounded by machinery. I don’t quite admit that; it
is the allowing machines to be our masters and not our servants
that so injures the beauty of life nowadays. In other
words, it is the token of the terrible crime we have fallen into
of using our control of the powers of Nature for the purpose of
enslaving people, we careless meantime of how much happiness we
rob their lives of.</p>
<p>Yet for the consolation of the artists I will say that I
believe indeed that a state of social order would probably lead
at first to a great development of machinery for really useful
purposes, because people will still be anxious about getting
through the work necessary to holding society together; but that
after a while they will find that there is not so much work to do
as they expected, and that then they will have leisure to
reconsider the whole subject; and if it seems to them that a
certain industry would be carried on more pleasantly as regards
the worker, and more effectually as regards the goods, by using
hand-work rather than machinery, they will certainly get rid of
their machinery, because it will be possible for them to do
so. It isn’t possible now; we are not at liberty to
do so; we are slaves to the monsters which we have created.
And I have a kind of hope that the very elaboration of machinery
in a society whose purpose is not the multiplication of labour,
as it now is, but the carrying on of a pleasant life, as it would
be under social order—that the elaboration of machinery, I
say, will lead the simplification of life, and so once more to
the limitation of machinery.</p>
<p>Well, I will now let my claims for decent life stand as I have
made them. To sum them up in brief, they are: First, a
healthy body; second, an active mind in sympathy with the past,
the present, and the future; thirdly, occupation fit for a
healthy body and an active mind; and fourthly, a beautiful world
to live in.</p>
<p>These are the conditions of life which the refined man of all
ages has set before him as the thing above all others to be
attained. Too often he has been so foiled in their pursuit
that he has turned longing eyes backward to the days before
civilization, when man’s sole business was getting himself
food from day to day, and hope was dormant in him, or at least
could not be expressed by him.</p>
<p>Indeed, if civilization (as many think) forbids the
realization of the hope to attain such conditions of life, then
civilization forbids mankind to be happy; and if that be the
case, then let us stifle all aspirations towards
progress—nay, all feelings of mutual good-will and
affection between men—and snatch each one of us what we can
from the heap of wealth that fools create for rogues to grow fat
on; or better still, let us as speedily as possible find some
means of dying like men, since we are forbidden to live like
men.</p>
<p>Rather, however, take courage, and believe that we of this
age, in spite of all its torment and disorder, have been born to
a wonderful heritage fashioned of the work of those that have
gone before us; and that the day of the organization of man is
dawning. It is not we who can build up the new social
order; the past ages have done the most of that work for us; but
we can clear our eyes to the signs of the times, and we shall
then see that the attainment of a good condition of life is being
made possible for us, and that it is now our business to stretch
out our hands to take it.</p>
<p>And how? Chiefly, I think, by educating people to a
sense of their real capacities as men, so that they may be able
to use to their own good the political power which is rapidly
being thrust upon them; to get them to see that the old system of
organizing labour <i>for individual profit</i> is becoming
unmanageable, and that the whole people have now got to choose
between the confusion resulting from the break up of that system
and the determination to take in hand the labour now organized
for profit, and use its organization for the livelihood of the
community: to get people to see that individual profit-makers are
not a necessity for labour but an obstruction to it, and that not
only or chiefly because they are the perpetual pensioners of
labour, as they are, but rather because of the waste which their
existence as a class necessitates. All this we have to
teach people, when we have taught ourselves; and I admit that the
work is long and burdensome; as I began by saying, people have
been made so timorous of change by the terror of starvation that
even the unluckiest of them are stolid and hard to move.
Hard as the work is, however, its reward is not doubtful.
The mere fact that a body of men, however small, are banded
together as Socialist missionaries shows that the change is going
on. As the working-classes, the real organic part of
society, take in these ideas, hope will arise in them, and they
will claim changes in society, many of which doubtless will not
tend directly towards their emancipation, because they will be
claimed without due knowledge of the one thing necessary to
claim, <i>equality of condition</i>; but which indirectly will
help to break up our rotten sham society, while that claim for
equality of condition will be made constantly and with growing
loudness till it <i>must</i> be listened to, and then at last it
will only be a step over the border and the civilized world will
be socialized; and, looking back on what has been, we shall be
astonished to think of how long we submitted to live as we live
now.</p>
<h2><SPAN name="page37"></SPAN><span class="pagenum"></span>WHIGS, DEMOCRATS, AND SOCIALISTS. <SPAN name="citation37a"></SPAN><SPAN href="#footnote37a" class="citation">[37a]</SPAN></h2>
<p><span class="smcap">What</span> is the state of parties in
England to-day? How shall we enumerate them? The
Whigs, who stand first on the list in my title, are considered
generally to be the survival of an old historical party once
looked on as having democratic tendencies, but now the hope of
all who would stand soberly on the ancient ways. Besides
these, there are Tories also, the descendants of the stout
defenders of Church and State and the divine right of kings.</p>
<p>Now, I don’t mean to say but that at the back of this
ancient name of Tory there lies a great mass of genuine
Conservative feeling, held by people who, if they had their own
way, would play some rather fantastic tricks, I fancy; nay, even
might in the course of time be somewhat rough with such people as
are in this hall at present. <SPAN name="citation37b"></SPAN><SPAN href="#footnote37b" class="citation">[37b]</SPAN> But this
feeling, after all, is only a sentiment now; all practical hope
has died out of it, and these worthy people <i>cannot</i> have
their own way. It is true that they elect members of
Parliament, who talk very big to please them, and sometimes even
they manage to get a Government into power that nominally
represents their sentiment, but when that happens the said
Government is forced, even when its party has a majority in the
House of Commons, to take a much lower standpoint than the high
Tory ideal; the utmost that the real Tory party can do, even when
backed by the Primrose League and its sham hierarchy, is to
delude the electors to return Tories to Parliament to pass
measures more akin to Radicalism than the Whigs durst attempt, so
that, though there are Tories, there is no Tory party in
England.</p>
<p>On the other hand, there is a party, which I can call for the
present by no other name than Whig, which is both numerous and
very powerful, and which does, in fact, govern England, and to my
mind will always do so as long as the present constitutional
Parliament lasts. Of course, like all parties it includes
men of various shades of opinion, from the Tory-tinted Whiggery
of Lord Salisbury to the Radical-tinted Whiggery of Mr.
Chamberlain’s present tail. Neither do I mean to say
that they are conscious of being a united party; on the contrary,
the groups will sometimes oppose each other furiously at
elections, and perhaps the more simple-minded of them really
think that it is a matter of importance to the nation which
section of them may be in power; but they may always be reckoned
upon to be in their places and vote against any measure which
carries with it a real attack on our constitutional system;
surely very naturally, since they are there for no other purpose
than to do so. They are, and always must be, conscious
defenders of the present system, political and economical, as
long as they have any cohesion as Tories, Whigs, Liberals, or
even Radicals. Not one of them probably would go such a
very short journey towards revolution as the abolition of the
House of Lords. A one-chamber Parliament would seem to them
an impious horror, and the abolition of the monarchy they would
consider a serious inconvenience to the London tradesman.</p>
<p>Now this is the real Parliamentary Party, at present divided
into jarring sections under the influence of the survival of the
party warfare of the last few generations, but which already
shows signs of sinking its differences so as to offer a solid
front of resistance to the growing instinct which on its side
will before long result in a party claiming full economical as
well as political freedom for the whole people.</p>
<p>But is there nothing in Parliament, or seeking entrance to it,
except this variously tinted Whiggery, this Harlequin of
Reaction? Well, inside Parliament, setting aside the Irish
party, which is, we may now well hope, merely temporarily there,
there is not much. It is not among people of “wealth
and local influence,” who I see are supposed to be the only
available candidates for Parliament of a recognized party, that
you will find the elements of revolution. We will grant
that there are some few genuine Democrats there, and let them
pass. But outside there are undoubtedly many who are
genuine Democrats, and who have it in their heads that it is both
possible and desirable to capture the constitutional Parliament
and turn it into a real popular assembly, which, with the people
behind it, might lead us peaceably and constitutionally into the
great Revolution which all <i>thoughtful</i> men desire to bring
about; all thoughtful men, that is, who do not belong to the
consciously cynical Tories, <i>i.e.</i>, men determined, whether
it be just or unjust, good for humanity or bad for it, to keep
the people down as long as they can, which they hope, very
naturally, will be as long as they live.</p>
<p>To capture Parliament and turn it into a popular but
constitutional assembly is, I must conclude, the aspiration of
the genuine Democrats wherever they may be found; that is their
idea of the first step of the Democratic policy. The
questions to be asked of this, as of all other policies, are
first, What is the end proposed by it? and secondly, Are they
likely to succeed? As to the end proposed, I think there is
much difference of opinion. Some Democrats would answer
from the merely political point of view, and say: Universal
suffrage, payment of members, annual Parliaments, abolition of
the House of Lords, abolition of the monarchy, and so
forth. I would answer this by saying: After all, these are
not ends, but means to an end; and passing by the fact that the
last two are not constitutional measures, and so could not be
brought about without actual rebellion, I would say if you had
gained all these things, and more, all you would have done would
have been to establish the ascendancy of the Democratic party;
having so established it, you would then have to find out by the
usual party means what that Democratic party meant, and you would
find that your triumph in mere politics would lead you back again
exactly to the place you started from. You would be Whigs
under a different name. Monarchy, House of Lords, pensions,
standing army, and the rest of it, are only supports to the
present social system—the <i>privilege</i> based on the
wages and capital system of production—and are worth
nothing except as supports to it. If you are determined to
support that system, therefore, you had better leave these things
alone. The real masters of Society, the real tyrants of the
people, are the Landlords and Capitalists, whom your political
triumph would not interfere with.</p>
<p>Then, as now, there would be a proletariat and a moneyed
class. Then, as now, it would be possible sometimes for a
diligent, energetic man, with his mind set wholly on such
success, to climb out of the proletariat into the moneyed class,
there to sweat as he once was sweated; which, my friends, is, if
you will excuse the word, your ridiculous idea of freedom of
contract.</p>
<p>The sole and utmost success of your policy would be that it
might raise up a strong opposition to the condition of things
which it would be your function to uphold; but most probably such
opposition would still be outside Parliament, and not in it; you
would have made a revolution, probably not without bloodshed,
only to show people the necessity for another revolution the very
next day.</p>
<p>Will you think the example of America too trite? Anyhow,
consider it! A country with universal suffrage, no king, no
House of Lords, no privilege as you fondly think; only a little
standing army, chiefly used for the murder of red-skins; a
democracy after your model; and with all that, a society corrupt
to the core, and at this moment engaged in suppressing freedom
with just the same reckless brutality and blind ignorance as the
Czar of all the Russias uses. <SPAN name="citation43"></SPAN><SPAN href="#footnote43" class="citation">[43]</SPAN></p>
<p>But it will be said, and certainly with much truth, that not
all the Democrats are for mere political reform. I say that
I believe that this is true, and it is a very important truth
too. I will go farther, and will say that all those
Democrats who can be distinguished from Whigs do intend social
reforms which they hope will somewhat alter the relations of the
classes towards each other; and there is, generally speaking,
amongst Democrats a leaning towards a kind of limited
State-Socialism, and it is through that that they hope to bring
about a peaceful revolution, which, if it does not introduce a
condition of equality, will at least make the workers better off
and contented with their lot.</p>
<p>They hope to get a body of representatives elected to
Parliament, and by them to get measure after measure passed which
will tend towards this goal; nor would some of them, perhaps most
of them, be discontented if by this means we could glide into
complete State-Socialism. I think that the present
Democrats are widely tinged with this idea, and to me it is a
matter of hope that it is so; whatever of error there is in it,
it means advance beyond the complete barrenness of the mere
political programme.</p>
<p>Yet I must point out to these semi-Socialist Democrats that in
the first place they will be made the cat’s-paw of some of
the wilier of the Whigs. There are several of these
measures which look to some Socialistic, as, for instance, the
allotments scheme, and other schemes tending toward peasant
proprietorship, co-operation, and the like, but which after all,
in spite of their benevolent appearance, are really weapons in
the hands of reactionaries, having for their real object the
creation of a new middle-class made out of the working-class and
at their expense; the raising, in short, of a new army against
the attack of the disinherited.</p>
<p>There is no end to this kind of dodge, nor will be apparently
till there is an end of the class which tries it on; and a great
many of the Democrats will be amused and absorbed by it from time
to time. They call this sort of nonsense
“practical;” it <i>seems</i> like doing something,
while the steady propaganda of a principle which must prevail in
the end is, according to them, doing nothing, and is
unpractical. For the rest, it is not likely to become
dangerous, further than as it clogs the wheels of the real
movement somewhat, because it is sometimes a mere piece of
reaction, as when, for instance, it takes the form of peasant
proprietorship, flying right in the face of the commercial
development of the day, which tends ever more and more towards
the aggregation of capital, thereby smoothing the way for the
organized possession of the means of production by the workers
when the true revolution shall come: while, on the other hand,
when this attempt to manufacture a new middle-class takes the
form of co-operation and the like, it is not dangerous, because
it means nothing more than a slightly altered form of
joint-stockery, and everybody almost is beginning to see
this. The greed of men stimulated by the spectacle of
profit-making all around them, and also by the burden of the
interest on the money which they have been obliged to borrow,
will not allow them even to approach a true system of
co-operation. Those benefited by the transaction presently
become eager shareholders in a commercial speculation, and if
they are working-men, as they often are, they are also
capitalists. The enormous commercial success of the great
co-operative societies, and the absolute no-effect of that
success on the social conditions of the workers, are sufficient
tokens of what this non-political co-operation must come to:
“Nothing—it shall not be less.”</p>
<p>But again, it may be said, some of the Democrats go farther
than this; they take up actual pieces of Socialism, and are more
than inclined to support them. Nationalization of the land,
or of railways, or cumulative taxation on incomes, or limiting
the right of inheritance, or new factory laws, or the restriction
by law of the day’s labour—one of these, or more than
one sometimes, the Democrats will support, and see absolute
salvation in these one or two planks of the platform. All
this I admit, and once again say it is a hopeful sign, and yet
once again I say there is a snare in it—a snake lies
lurking in the grass.</p>
<p>Those who think that they can deal with our present system in
this piecemeal way very much underrate the strength of the
tremendous organization under which we live, and which appoints
to each of us his place, and if we do not chance to fit it,
grinds us down till we do. Nothing but a tremendous force
can deal with this force; it will not suffer itself to be
dismembered, nor to lose anything which really is its essence
without putting forth all its force in resistance; rather than
lose anything which it considers of importance, it will pull the
roof of the world down upon its head. For, indeed, I grant
these semi-Socialist Democrats that there is one hope for their
tampering piecemeal with our Society; if by chance they can
excite people into seriously, however blindly, claiming one or
other of these things in question, and could be successful in
Parliament in driving it through, they would certainly draw on a
great civil war, and such a war once let loose would not end but
either with the full triumph of Socialism or its extinction for
the present; it would be impossible to limit the aim of the
struggle; nor can we even guess at the course which it would
take, except that it could not be a matter of compromise.
But suppose the Democratic party peaceably successful on this new
basis of semi-State Socialism, what would it all mean?
Attempts to balance the two classes whose interests are opposed
to each other, a mere ignoring of this antagonism which has led
us through so many centuries to where we are now, and then, after
a period of disappointment and disaster, the naked conflict once
more; a revolution made, and another immediately necessary on its
morrow!</p>
<p>Yet, indeed, it will not come to that; for, whatever may be
the aims of the Democrats, they will not succeed in getting
themselves into a position from whence they could make the
attempt to realize them. I have said there are Tories and
yet no real Tory party; so also it seems to me that there are
Democrats but no Democratic party; at present they are used by
the leaders of the parliamentary factions, and also kept at a
distance by them from any real power. If they by hook or
crook managed to get a number of members into Parliament, they
would find out their differences very speedily under the
influence of party rule; in point of fact, the Democrats are not
a party; because they have no principles other than the old
Whig-Radical ones, extended in some cases so as to take in a
little semi-Socialism which the march of events has forced on
them—that is, they gravitate on one side to the Whigs and
on the other to the Socialists. Whenever, if ever, they
begin to be a power in the elections and get members in the
House, the temptation to be members of a real live party which
may have the government of the country in its hands, the
temptation to what is (facetiously, I suppose) called practical
politics, will be too much for many, even of those who gravitate
towards Socialism; a quasi-Democratic parliamentary party,
therefore, would probably be merely a recruiting ground, a
nursery for the left wing of the Whigs; though it would indeed
leave behind some small nucleus of opposition, the principles of
which, however, would be vague and floating, so that it would be
but a powerless group after all.</p>
<p>The future of the constitutional Parliament, therefore, it
seems to me, is a perpetual Whig Rump, which will yield to
pressure when mere political reforms are attempted to be got out
of it, but will be quite immovable towards any real change in
social and economical matters; that is to say, so far as it may
be conscious of the attack; for I grant that it may be
<i>betrayed</i> into passing semi-State-Socialistic measures,
which will do this amount of good, that they will help to
entangle commerce in difficulties, and so add to discontent by
creating suffering; suffering of which the people will not
understand the causes definitely, but which their instinct will
tell them truly is brought about by <i>government</i>, and that,
too, the only kind of government which they can have so long as
the constitutional Parliament lasts.</p>
<p>Now, if you think I have exaggerated the power of the Whigs,
that is, of solid, dead, unmoving resistance to progress, I must
call your attention to the events of the last few weeks.
Here has been a measure of pacification proposed; at the least
and worst an attempt to enter upon a pacification of a weary and
miserable quarrel many centuries old. The British people,
in spite of their hereditary prejudice against the Irish, were
not averse to the measure; the Tories were, as usual, powerless
against it; yet so strong has been the <i>vis inertiæ</i>
of Whiggery that it has won a notable victory over common-sense
and sentiment combined, and has drawn over to it a section of
those hitherto known as Radicals, and probably would have drawn
all Radicals over but for the personal ascendancy of Mr.
Gladstone. The Whigs, seeing, if but dimly, that this Irish
Independence meant an attack on property, have been successful in
snatching the promised peace out of the people’s hands, and
in preparing all kinds of entanglement and confusion for us for a
long while in their steady resistance to even the beginnings of
revolution.</p>
<p>This, therefore, is what Parliament looks to me: a solid
central party, with mere nebulous opposition on the right hand
and on the left. The people governed; that is to say, fair
play amongst themselves for the money-privileged classes to make
the most of their privilege, and to fight sturdily with each
other in doing so; but the government concealed as much as
possible, and also as long as possible; that is to say, the
government resting on an assumed necessary eternity of privilege
to monopolize the means of the fructification of labour.</p>
<p>For so long as that assumption is accepted by the ignorance of
the people, the Great Whig Rump will remain inexpugnable, but as
soon as the people’s eyes are opened, even
partially—and they begin to understand the meaning of the
words, the Emancipation of Labour—we shall begin to have an
assured hope of throwing off the basest and most sordid tyranny
which the world has yet seen, the tyranny of so-called
Constitutionalism.</p>
<p>How, then, are the people’s eyes to be opened? By
the force evolved from the final triumph and consequent
corruption of Commercial Whiggery, which force will include in it
a recognition of its constructive activity by intelligent people
on the one hand, and on the other half-blind instinctive
struggles to use its destructive activity on the part of those
who suffer and have not been allowed to think; and, to boot, a
great deal that goes between those two extremes.</p>
<p>In this turmoil, all those who can be truly called Socialists
will be involved. The modern development of the great
class-struggle has forced us to think, our thoughts force us to
speak, and our hopes force us to try to get a hearing from the
people. Nor can one tell how far our words will carry, so
to say. The most moderate exposition of our principles will
bear with it the seeds of disruption; nor can we tell what form
that disruption will take.</p>
<p>One and all, then, we are responsible for the enunciation of
Socialist principles and of the consequences which may flow from
their general acceptance, whatever that may be. This
responsibility no Socialist can shake off by declarations against
physical force and in favour of constitutional methods of
agitation; we are attacking the Constitution with the very
beginnings, the mere lispings, of Socialism.</p>
<p>Whiggery, therefore, in its various forms, is the
representative of Constitutionalism—is the outward
expression of monopoly and consequent artificial restraints on
labour and life; and there is only one expression of the force
which will destroy Whiggery, and that is Socialism; and on the
right hand and on the left Toryism and Radicalism will melt into
Whiggery—are doing so now—and Socialism has got to
absorb all that is not Whig in Radicalism.</p>
<p>Then comes the question, What is the policy of
Socialism? If Toryism and Democracy are only nebulous
masses of opposition to the solid centre of Whiggery, what can we
call Socialism?</p>
<p>Well, at present, in England at least, Socialism is not a
party, but a sect. That is sometimes brought against it as
a taunt; but I am not dismayed by it; for I can conceive of a
sect—nay, I have heard of one—becoming a very
formidable power, and becoming so by dint of its long remaining a
sect. So I think it is quite possible that Socialism will
remain a sect till the very eve of the last stroke that completes
the revolution, after which it will melt into the new
Society. And is it not sects, bodies of definite,
uncompromising principles, that lead us into revolutions?
Was it not so in the Cromwellian times? Nay, have not the
Fenian sect, even in our own days, made Home Rule possible?
They may give birth to parties, though not parties
themselves. And what should a sect like we are have to do
in the parliamentary struggle—we who have an ideal to keep
always before ourselves and others, and who cannot accept
compromise; who can see nothing that can give us rest for a
minute save the emancipation of labour, which will be brought
about by the workers gaining possession of all the means of the
fructification of labour; and who, even when that is gained,
shall have pure Communism ahead to strive for?</p>
<p>What are we to do, then? Stand by and look on? Not
exactly. Yet we may look on other people doing their work
while we do ours. They are already beginning, as I have
said, to stumble about with attempts at State Socialism.
Let them make their experiments and blunders, and prepare the way
for us by so doing. And our own business? Well,
we—sect or party, or group of self-seekers, madmen, and
poets, which you will—are at least the only set of people
who have been able to see that there is and has been a great
class-struggle going on. Further, we can see that this
class-struggle cannot come to an end till the classes themselves
do: one class must absorb the other. Which, then?
Surely the useful one, the one that the world lives by, and
on. The business of the people at present is to make it
impossible for the useless, non-producing class to live; while
the business of Constitutionalism is, on the contrary, to make it
possible for them to live. And our business is to help to
make the people <i>conscious</i> of this great antagonism between
the people and Constitutionalism; and meantime to let
Constitutionalism go on with its government unhelped by us at
least, until it at last becomes <i>conscious</i> of its burden of
the people’s hate, of the people’s knowledge that it
is disinherited, which we shall have done our best to further by
any means that we could.</p>
<p>As to Socialists in Parliament, there are two words about
that. If they go there to take a part in carrying on
Constitutionalism by palliating the evils of the system, and so
helping our rulers to bear their burden of government, I for one,
and so far as their action therein goes, cannot call them
Socialists at all. But if they go there with the intention
of doing what they can towards the disruption of Parliament, that
is a matter of tactics for the time being; but even here I cannot
help seeing the danger of their being seduced from their true
errand, and I fear that they might become, on the terms above
mentioned, simply supporters of the very thing they set out to
undo.</p>
<p>I say that our work lies quite outside Parliament, and it is
to help to educate the people by every and any means that may be
effective; and the knowledge we have to help them to is
threefold—to know their own, to know how to take their own,
and to know how to use their own.</p>
<h2><SPAN name="page55"></SPAN><span class="pagenum"></span>FEUDAL ENGLAND.</h2>
<p><span class="smcap">It</span> is true that the Norman Conquest
found a certain kind of feudality in existence in England—a
feudality which was developed from the customs of the Teutonic
tribes with no admixture of Roman law; and also that even before
the Conquest this country was slowly beginning to be mixed up
with the affairs of the Continent of Europe, and that not only
with the kindred nations of Scandinavia, but with the Romanized
countries also. But the Conquest of Duke William did
introduce the complete Feudal system into the country; and it
also connected it by strong bonds to the Romanized countries, and
yet by so doing laid the first foundations of national feeling in
England. The English felt their kinship with the Norsemen
or the Danes, and did not suffer from their conquests when they
had become complete, and when, consequently, mere immediate
violence had disappeared from them; their feeling was tribal
rather than national; but they could have no sense of tribal
unity with the varied populations of the provinces which mere
dynastical events had strung together into the dominion, the
manor, one may say, of the foreign princes of Normandy and Anjou;
and, as the kings who ruled them gradually got pushed out of
their French possessions, England began to struggle against the
domination of men felt to be foreigners, and so gradually became
conscious of her separate nationality, though still only in a
fashion, as the manor of an <i>English</i> lord.</p>
<p>It is beyond the scope of this piece to give anything like a
connected story, even of the slightest, of the course of events
between the conquest of Duke William and the fully developed
mediæval period of the fourteenth century, which is the
England that I have before my eyes as Mediæval or
Feudal. That period of the fourteenth century united the
developments of the elements which had been stirring in Europe
since the final fall of the Roman Empire, and England shared in
the general feeling and spirit of the age, although, from its
position, the course of its history, and to a certain extent the
lives of its people, were different. It is to this period,
therefore, that I wish in the long run to call your attention,
and I will only say so much about the earlier period as may be
necessary to explain how the people of England got into the
position in which they were found by the Statute of Labourers
enacted by Edward III., and the Peasants’ Rebellion in the
time of his grandson and successor, Richard II.</p>
<p>Undoubtedly, then, the Norman Conquest made a complete break
in the continuity of the history of England. When the
Londoners after the Battle of Hastings accepted Duke William for
their king, no doubt they thought of him as occupying much the
same position as that of the newly slain Harold; or at any rate
they looked on him as being such a king of England as Knut the
Dane, who had also conquered the country; and probably William
himself thought no otherwise; but the event was quite different;
for on the one hand, not only was he a man of strong character,
able, masterful, and a great soldier in the modern sense of the
word, but he had at his back his wealthy dukedom of Normandy,
which he had himself reduced to obedience and organized; and, on
the other hand, England lay before him, unorganized, yet
stubbornly rebellious to him; its very disorganization and want
of a centre making it more difficult to deal with by merely
overrunning it with an army levied for that purpose, and backed
by a body of house-carles or guards, which would have been the
method of a Scandinavian or native king in dealing with his
rebellious subjects. Duke William’s necessities and
instincts combined led him into a very different course of
action, which determined the future destiny of the country.
What he did was to quarter upon England an army of feudal vassals
drawn from his obedient dukedom, and to hand over to them the
lordship of the land of England in return for their military
service to him, the suzerain of them all. Thenceforward, it
was under the rule of these foreign landlords that the people of
England had to develop.</p>
<p>The development of the country as a Teutonic people was
checked and turned aside by this event. Duke William
brought, in fact, his Normandy into England, which was thereby
changed from a Teutonic people (Old-Norse theod), with the tribal
customary law still in use among them, into a province of
Romanized Feudal Europe, a piece of France, in short; and though
in time she did grow into another England again, she missed for
ever in her laws, and still more in her language and her
literature, the chance of developing into a great homogeneous
Teutonic people infused usefully with a mixture of Celtic
blood.</p>
<p>However, this step which Duke William was forced to take
further influenced the future of the country by creating the
great order of the Baronage, and the history of the early period
of England is pretty much that of the struggle of the king with
the Baronage and the Church. For William fixed the type of
the successful English mediæval king, of whom Henry II. and
Edward I. were the most notable examples afterwards. It
was, in fact, with him that the struggle towards monarchical
bureaucracy began, which was checked by the barons, who extorted
Magna Charta from King John, and afterwards by the revolt headed
by Simon de Montfort in Henry III.’s reign; was carried on
vigorously by Edward I., and finally successfully finished by
Henry VII. after the long faction-fight of the Wars of the Roses
had weakened the feudal lords so much that they could no longer
assert themselves against the monarchy.</p>
<p>As to the other political struggle of the Middle Ages, the
contest between the Crown and the Church, two things are to be
noted; first, that at least in the earlier period the Church was
on the popular side. Thomas Beckett was canonized, it is
true, formally and by regular decree; but his memory was held so
dear by the people that he would probably have been canonized
informally by them if the holy seat at Rome had refused to do
so. The second thing to be noted about the dispute is this,
that it was no contest of principle. According to the
mediæval theory of life and religion, the Church and the
State were one in essence, and but separate manifestations of the
Kingdom of God upon earth, which was part of the Kingdom of God
in heaven. The king was an officer of that realm and a
liegeman of God. The doctor of laws and the doctor of
physic partook in a degree of the priestly character. On
the other hand, the Church was not withdrawn from the every-day
life of men; the division into a worldly and spiritual life,
neither of which had much to do with the other, was a creation of
the protestantism of the Reformation, and had no place in the
practice at least of the mediæval Church, which we cannot
too carefully remember is little more represented by modern
Catholicism than by modern Protestantism. The contest,
therefore, between the Crown and the Church was a mere bickering
between two bodies, without any essential antagonism between
them, as to how far the administration of either reached; neither
dreamed of subordinating one to the other, far less of
extinguishing one by the other.</p>
<p>The history of the Crusades, by-the-way, illustrates very
emphatically this position of the Church in the Middle
Ages. The foundation of that strange feudal kingdom of
Jerusalem, whose very coat of arms was a solecism in heraldry,
whose king had precedence, in virtue of his place as lord of the
centre of Christianity, over all other kings and princes; the
orders of men-at-arms vowed to poverty and chastity, like the
Templars and Knights of St. John; and above all the unquestioning
sense of duty that urged men of all classes and kinds into the
holy war, show how strongly the idea of God’s Kingdom on
the earth had taken hold of all men’s minds in the early
Middle Ages. As to the result of the Crusades, they
certainly had their influence on the solidification of Europe and
the great feudal system, at the head of which, in theory at
least, were the Pope and the Kaiser. For the rest, the
intercourse with the East gave Europe an opportunity of sharing
in the mechanical civilization of the peoples originally
dominated by the Arabs, and infused by the art of Byzantium and
Persia, not without some tincture of the cultivation of the
latter classical period.</p>
<p>The stir and movement also of the Crusades, and the
necessities in which they involved the princes and their barons,
furthered the upward movement of the classes that lay below the
feudal vassals, great and little; the principal opportunity for
which movement, however, in England, was given by the continuous
struggle between the Crown and the Church and Baronage.</p>
<p>The early Norman kings, even immediately after the death of
the Conqueror, found themselves involved in this struggle, and
were forced to avail themselves of the help of what had now
become the inferior tribe—the native English, to wit.
Henry I., an able and ambitious man, understood this so clearly
that he made a distinct bid for the favour of the inferior tribe
by marrying an English princess; and it was by means of the help
of his English subjects that he conquered his Norman subjects,
and the field of Tenchebray, which put the coping-stone on his
success, was felt by the English people as an English victory
over the oppressing tribe with which Duke William had overwhelmed
the English people. It was during this king’s reign
and under these influences that the trading and industrial
classes began to rise somewhat. The merchant gilds were now
in their period of greatest power, and had but just begun, in
England at least, to develop into the corporations of the towns;
but the towns themselves were beginning to gain their freedom and
to become an important element in the society of the time, as
little by little they asserted themselves against the arbitrary
rule of the feudal lords, lay or ecclesiastical: for as to the
latter, it must be remembered that the Church included in herself
the orders or classes into which lay society was divided, and
while by its lower clergy of the parishes and by the friars it
touched the people, its upper clergy were simply feudal lords;
and as the religious fervour of the higher clergy, which was
marked enough in the earlier period of the Middle Ages (in
Anselm, for example), faded out, they became more and more mere
landlords, although from the conditions of their landlordism,
living as they did on their land and amidst of their tenants,
they were less oppressive than the lay landlords.</p>
<p>The order and progress of Henry I.’s reign, which marks
the transition from the mere military camp of the Conqueror to
the mediæval England I have to dwell upon, was followed by
the period of mere confusion and misery which accompanied the
accession of the princes of Anjou to the throne of England.
In this period the barons widely became mere violent and illegal
robbers; and the castles with which the land was dotted, and
which were begun under the auspices of the Conqueror as military
posts, became mere dens of strong-thieves.</p>
<p>No doubt this made the business of the next able king, Henry
II., the easier. He was a staunch man of business, and
turned himself with his whole soul towards the establishment of
order and the consolidation of the monarchy, which accordingly
took a great stride under him towards its ultimate goal of
bureaucracy. He would probably have carried the business
still farther, since in his contest with the Church, in spite of
the canonization of Beckett and the king’s formal penance
at his tomb, he had in fact gained a victory for the Crown which
it never really lost again; but in his days England was only a
part of the vast dominion of his House, which included more than
half of France, and his struggle with his feudatories and the
French king, which sowed the seed of the loss of that dominion to
the English Crown, took up much of his life, and finally beat
him.</p>
<p>His two immediate successors, Richard I. and John, were good
specimens of the chiefs of their line, almost all of whom were
very able men, having even a touch of genius in them, but
therewithal were such wanton blackguards and scoundrels that one
is almost forced to apply the theological word
“wickedness” to them. Such characters belong
specially to their times, fertile as they were both of great
qualities and of scoundrelism, and in which our own special vice
of hypocrisy was entirely lacking. John, the second of
these two pests, put the coping-stone on the villany of his
family, and lost his French dominion in the lump.</p>
<p>Under such rascals as these came the turn of the Baronage; and
they, led by Stephen Langton, the archbishop who had been thrust
on the unwilling king by the Pope, united together and forced
from him his assent to Magna Charta, the great, thoroughly
well-considered deed, which is conventionally called the
foundation of English Liberty, but which can only claim to be so
on the ground that it was the confirmation and seal of the
complete feudal system in England, and put the relations between
the vassals, the great feudatories, and the king on a stable
basis; since it created, or at least confirmed, order among these
privileged classes, among whom, indeed, it recognized the towns
to a certain extent as part of the great feudal hierarchy: so
that even by this time they had begun to acquire status in that
hierarchy.</p>
<p>So John passed away, and became not long after an almost
mythical personage, the type of the bad king. There are
still ballads, and prose stories deduced from these ballads, in
existence, which tell the tale of this strange monster as the
English people imagined it.</p>
<p>As they belong to the literature of the fourteenth century,
the period I have undertaken to tell you about specially, I will
give you one of the latter of these concerning the death of King
John, for whom the people imagined a more dramatic cause of death
than mere indigestion, of which in all probability he really
died; and you may take it for a specimen of popular literature of
the fourteenth century.</p>
<p>I can here make bold to quote from memory, without departing
very widely from the old text, since the quaint wording of the
original, and the spirit of bold and blunt heroism which it
breathes, have fixed it in my mind for ever.</p>
<p>The king, you must remember, had halted at Swinestead Abbey,
in Lincolnshire, in his retreat from the hostile barons and their
French allies, and had lost all his baggage by the surprise of
the advancing tide in the Wash; so that he might well be in a
somewhat sour mood.</p>
<p>Says the tale: So the king went to meat in the hall, and
before him was a loaf; and he looked grimly on it and said,
‘For how much is such a loaf sold in this realm?’</p>
<p>‘Sir, for one penny,’ said they.</p>
<p>Then the king smote the board with his fist and said,
‘By God, if I live for one year such a loaf shall be sold
for twelve pence!’</p>
<p>That heard one of the monks who stood thereby, and he thought
and considered that his hour and time to die was come, and that
it would be a good deed to slay so cruel a king and so evil a
lord.</p>
<p>So he went into the garden and plucked plums and took out of
them the steles [stalks], and did venom in them each one; and he
came before the king and sat on his knee, and said:</p>
<p>‘Sir, by St. Austin, this is fruit of our
garden.’</p>
<p>Then the king looked evilly on him and said, ‘Assay
them, monk!’</p>
<p>So the monk took and ate thereof, nor changed countenance any
whit: and the king ate thereafter.</p>
<p>But presently afterwards the monk swelled and turned blue, and
fell down and died before the king: then waxed the king sick at
heart, and he also swelled and died, and so he ended his
days.</p>
<p>For a while after the death of John and the accession of Henry
III. the Baronage, strengthened by the great Charter and with a
weak and wayward king on the throne, made their step forward in
power and popularity, and the first serious check to the tendency
to monarchical bureaucracy, a kind of elementary aristocratic
constitution, was imposed upon the weakness of Henry III.
Under this movement of the barons, who in their turn had to seek
for the support of the people, the towns made a fresh step in
advance, and Simon de Montfort, the leader of what for want of a
better word must be called the popular party, was forced by his
circumstances to summon to his Parliament citizens from the
boroughs. Earl Simon was one of those men that come to the
front in violent times, and he added real nobility of character
to strength of will and persistence. He became the hero of
the people, who went near to canonizing him after his
death. But the monarchy was too strong for him and his
really advanced projects, which by no means squared with the
hopes of the Baronage in general: and when Prince Edward,
afterwards Edward I., grown to his full mental stature, came to
the help of the Crown with his unscrupulous business ability, the
struggle was soon over; and with Evesham field the monarchy began
to take a new stride, and the longest yet taken, towards
bureaucracy.</p>
<p>Edward I. is remembered by us chiefly for the struggle he
carried on with the Scotch Baronage for the feudal suzerainty of
that kingdom, and the centuries of animosity between the two
countries which that struggle drew on. But he has other
claims to our attention besides this.</p>
<p>At first, and remembering the ruthlessness of many of his
acts, especially in the Scotch war, one is apt to look upon him
as a somewhat pedantic tyrant and a good soldier, with something
like a dash of hypocrisy beyond his time added. But, like
the Angevine kings I was speaking of just now, he was a
completely characteristic product of his time. He was not a
hypocrite probably, after all, in spite of his tears shed after
he had irretrievably lost a game, or after he had won one by
stern cruelty. There was a dash of real romance in him,
which mingled curiously with his lawyer-like qualities. He
was, perhaps, the man of all men who represented most completely
the finished feudal system, and who took it most to heart.
His law, his romance, and his religion, his self-command, and his
terrible fury were all a part of this innate feudalism, and
exercised within its limits; and we must suppose that he
thoroughly felt his responsibility as the chief of his
feudatories, while at the same time he had no idea of his having
any responsibilities towards the lower part of his
subjects. Such a man was specially suited to carrying on
the tendency to bureaucratic centralization, which culminated in
the Tudor monarchy. He had his struggle with the Baronage,
but hard as it was, he was sure not to carry it beyond the due
limits of feudalism; to that he was always loyal. He had
slain Earl Simon before he was king, while he was but his
father’s general; but Earl Simon’s work did not die
with him, and henceforward, while the Middle Ages and their
feudal hierarchy lasted, it was impossible for either king or
barons to do anything which would seriously injure each
other’s position; the struggle ended in his reign in a
balance of power in England which, on the one hand, prevented any
great feudatory becoming a rival of the king, as happened in
several instances in France, and on the other hand prevented the
king lapsing into a mere despotic monarch.</p>
<p>I have said that bureaucracy took a great stride in
Edward’s reign, but it reached its limits under feudalism
as far as the nobles were concerned. Peace and order was
established between the different powers of the governing
classes; henceforward, the struggle is between them and the
governed; that struggle was now to become obvious; the lower
tribe was rising in importance; it was becoming richer for
fleecing, but also it was beginning to have some power; this led
the king first, and afterwards the barons, to attack it
definitely; it was rich enough to pay for the trouble of being
robbed, and not yet strong enough to defend itself with open
success, although the slower and less showy success of growth did
not fail it. The instrument of attack in the hands of the
barons was the ordinary feudal privilege, the logical carrying
out of serfdom; but this attack took place two reigns
later. We shall come to that further on. The attack
on the lower tribe which was now growing into importance was in
this reign made by the king; and his instrument
was—Parliament.</p>
<p>I have told you that Simon de Montfort made some attempt to
get the burgesses to sit in his Parliament, but it was left to
Edward I. to lay the foundations firmly of parliamentary
representation, which he used for the purpose of augmenting the
power of the Crown and crushing the rising liberty of the towns,
though of course his direct aim was simply at—money.</p>
<p>The Great Council of the Realm was purely feudal; it was
composed of the feudatories of the king, theoretically of all of
them, practically of the great ones only. It was, in fact,
the council of the conquering tribe with their chief at its head;
the matters of the due feudal tribute, aids, reliefs, fines,
scutage, and the like—in short, the king’s revenue
due from his men—were settled in this council at once and
in the lump. But the inferior tribe, though not represented
there, existed, and, as aforesaid, was growing rich, and the king
had to get their money out of their purses directly; which, as
they were not represented at the council, he had to do by means
of his officers (the sheriffs) dealing with them one after
another, which was a troublesome job; for the men were
stiff-necked and quite disinclined to part with their money; and
the robbery having to be done on the spot, so to say, encountered
all sorts of opposition: and, in fact, it was the money needs
both of baron, bishop, and king which had been the chief
instrument in furthering the progress of the towns. The
towns would be pressed by their lords, king, or baron, or bishop,
as it might be, and they would see their advantage and strike a
bargain. For you are not to imagine that because there was
a deal of violence going on in those times there was no respect
for law; on the contrary, there was a quite exaggerated respect
for it if it came within the four corners of the feudal feeling,
and the result of this feeling of respect was the constant
struggle for <i>status</i> on the part of the townships and other
associations throughout the Middle Ages.</p>
<p>Well, the burghers would say, “’Tis hard to pay
this money, but we will put ourselves out to pay it if you will
do something for us in return; let, for example, our men be tried
in our own court, and the verdict be of one of compurgation
instead of wager of battle,” and so forth, and so
forth.</p>
<p>All this sort of detailed bargaining was, in fact, a safeguard
for the local liberties, so far as they went, of the towns and
shires, and did not suit the king’s views of law and order
at all; and so began the custom of the sheriff (the king’s
officer, who had taken the place of the earl of the Anglo-Saxon
period) summoning the burgesses to the council, which burgesses
you must understand were not elected at the folkmotes of the
town, or hundred, but in a sort of hole-and-corner way by a few
of the bigger men of the place. What the king practically
said was this: “I want your money, and I cannot be for ever
wrangling with you stubborn churles at home there, and listening
to all your stories of how poor you are, and what you want; no, I
want you to be <i>represented</i>. Send me up from each one
of your communes a man or two whom I can bully or cajole or bribe
to sign away your substance for you.”</p>
<p>Under these circumstances it is no wonder that the towns were
not very eager in the cause of <i>representation</i>. It
was no easy job to get them to come up to London merely to
consult as to the kind of sauce with which they were to be
eaten. However, they did come in some numbers, and by the
year 1295 something like a shadow of our present Parliament was
on foot. Nor need there be much more said about this
institution; as time went on its functions got gradually extended
by the petition for the redress of grievances accompanying the
granting of money, but it was generally to be reckoned on as
subservient to the will of the king, who down to the later Tudor
period played some very queer tunes on this constitutional
instrument.</p>
<p>Edward I. gave place to his son, who again was of the type of
king who had hitherto given the opportunity to the barons for
their turn of advancement in the constitutional struggle; and in
earlier times no doubt they would have taken full advantage of
the circumstances; as it was they had little to gain. The
king did his best to throw off the restraint of the feudal
constitution, and to govern simply as an absolute monarch.
After a time of apparent success he failed, of course, and only
succeeded in confirming the legal rights of feudalism by bringing
about his own formal deposition at the hands of the Baronage, as
a chief who, having broken the compact with his feudatories, had
necessarily forfeited his right. If we compare his case
with that of Charles I. we shall find this difference in it,
besides the obvious one that Edward was held responsible to his
feudatories and Charles towards the upper middle classes, the
squirearchy, as represented by Parliament; that Charles was
condemned by a law created for the purpose, so to say, and
evolved from the principle of the representation of the
propertied classes, while Edward’s deposition was the real
logical outcome of the confirmed feudal system, and was
practically legal and regular.</p>
<p>The successor of the deposed king, the third Edward, ushers in
the complete and central period of the Middle Ages in
England. The feudal system is complete: the life and spirit
of the country has developed into a condition if not quite
independent, yet quite forgetful, on the one hand of the ideas
and customs of the Celtic and Teutonic tribes, and on the other
of the authority of the Roman Empire. The Middle Ages have
grown into manhood; that manhood has an art of its own, which,
though developed step by step from that of Old Rome and New Rome,
and embracing the strange mysticism and dreamy beauty of the
East, has forgotten both its father and its mother, and stands
alone triumphant, the loveliest, brightest, and gayest of all the
creations of the human mind and hand.</p>
<p>It has a literature of its own too, somewhat akin to its art,
yet inferior to it, and lacking its unity, since there is a
double stream in it. On the one hand is the court poet, the
gentleman, Chaucer, with his Italianizing metres, and his formal
recognition of the classical stories; on which, indeed, he builds
a superstructure of the quaintest and most unadulterated
mediævalism, as gay and bright as the architecture which
his eyes beheld and his pen pictured for us, so clear, defined,
and elegant it is; a sunny world even amidst its violence and
passing troubles, like those of a happy child, the worst of them
an amusement rather than a grief to the onlookers; a world that
scarcely needed hope in its eager life of adventure and love,
amidst the sunlit blossoming meadows, and green woods, and white
begilded manor-houses. A kindly and human muse is
Chaucer’s, nevertheless, interested in and amused by all
life, but of her very nature devoid of strong aspirations for the
future; and that all the more, since, though the strong devotion
and fierce piety of the ruder Middle Ages had by this time waned,
and the Church was more often lightly mocked at than either
feared or loved, still the <i>habit</i> of looking on this life
as part of another yet remained: the world is fair and full of
adventure; kind men and true and noble are in it to make one
happy; fools also to laugh at, and rascals to be resisted, yet
not wholly condemned; and when this world is over we shall still
go on living in another which is a part of this. Look at
all the picture, note all and live in all, and be as merry as you
may, never forgetting that you are alive and that it is good to
live.</p>
<p>That is the spirit of Chaucer’s poetry; but alongside of
it existed yet the ballad poetry of the people, wholly untouched
by courtly elegance and classical pedantry; rude in art but never
coarse, true to the backbone; instinct with indignation against
wrong, and thereby expressing the hope that was in it; a protest
of the poor against the rich, especially in those songs of the
Foresters, which have been called the mediæval epic of
revolt; no more gloomy than the gentleman’s poetry, yet
cheerful from courage, and not content. Half a dozen
stanzas of it are worth a cartload of the whining introspective
lyrics of to-day; and he who, when he has mastered the slight
differences of language from our own daily speech, is not moved
by it, does not understand what true poetry means nor what its
aim is.</p>
<p>There is a third element in the literature of this time which
you may call Lollard poetry, the great example of which is
William Langland’s “Piers Plowman.” It is
no bad corrective to Chaucer, and in <i>form</i> at least belongs
wholly to the popular side; but it seems to me to show symptoms
of the spirit of the rising middle class, and casts before it the
shadow of the new master that was coming forward for the
workman’s oppression. But I must leave what more I
have to say on this subject of the art and literature of the
fourteenth century for another occasion. In what I have
just said, I only wanted to point out to you that the Middle Ages
had by this time come to the fullest growth; and that they could
express in a form which was all their own, the ideas and life of
the time.</p>
<p>That time was in a sense brilliant and progressive, and the
life of the worker in it was better than it ever had been, and
might compare with advantage with what it became in after periods
and with what it is now; and indeed, looking back upon it, there
are some minds and some moods that cannot help regretting it, and
are not particularly scared by the idea of its violence and its
lack of accurate knowledge of scientific detail.</p>
<p>However, one thing is clear to us now, the kind of thing which
never is clear to most people living in such
periods—namely, that whatever it was, it could not last,
but must change into something else.</p>
<p>The complete feudalism of the fourteenth century fell, as
systems always fall, by its own corruption, and by development of
the innate seeds of change, some of which indeed had lain asleep
during centuries, to wake up into activity long after the events
which had created them were forgotten.</p>
<p>The feudal system was naturally one of open war; and the
alliances, marriages, and other dealings, family with family,
made by the king and potentates, were always leading them into
war by giving them legal claims, or at least claims that could be
legally pleaded, to the domains of other lords, who took
advantage of their being on the spot, of their strength in men or
money, or their popularity with the Baronage, to give immediate
effect to <i>their</i> claims. Such a war was that by which
Edward I. drew on England the enmity of the Scotch; and such
again was the great war which Edward III. entered into with
France. You must not suppose that there was anything in
this war of a national, far less of a race, character. The
last series of wars before this time I am now speaking of, in
which race feelings counted for much, was the Crusades.
This French war, I say, was neither national, racial, or tribal;
it was the private business of a lord of the manor, claiming what
he considered his legal rights of another lord, who had, as he
thought, usurped them; and this claim his loyal feudatories were
bound to take up for him; loyalty to a feudal superior, not
patriotism to a country, was the virtue which Edward III.’s
soldiers had to offer, if they had any call to be virtuous in
that respect.</p>
<p>This war once started was hard to drop, partly because of the
success that Edward had in it, falling as he did on France with
the force of a country so much more homogeneous than it; and no
doubt it was a war very disastrous to both countries, and so may
be reckoned as amongst the causes which broke up the feudal
system.</p>
<p>But the real causes of that break-up lay much deeper than
that. The system was not capable of expansion in
production; it was, in fact, as long as its integrity remained
untouched, an army fed by slaves, who could not be properly and
closely exploited; its free men proper might do something else in
their leisure, and so produce art and literature, but their true
business as members of a conquering tribe, their concerted
business, was to fight. There was, indeed, a fringe of
people between the serf and the free noble who produced the
matters of handicraft which were needed for the latter, but
deliberately, and, as we should now think, wastefully; and as
these craftsmen and traders began to grow into importance and to
push themselves, as they could not help doing, into the feudal
hierarchy, as they acquired <i>status</i>, so the sickness of the
feudal system increased on it, and the shadow of the coming
commercialism fell upon it.</p>
<p>That any set of people who could claim to be other than the
property of free men should not have definite rights
differentiated sharply from those of other groups, was an idea
that did not occur to the Middle Ages; therefore, as soon as men
came into existence that were not serfs and were not nobles, they
had to struggle for status by organizing themselves into
associations that should come to be acknowledged members of the
great feudal hierarchy; for indefinite and negative freedom was
not allowed to any person in those days; if you had not status
you did not exist except as an outlaw.</p>
<p>This is, briefly speaking, the motive power of necessity that
lay behind the struggle of the town corporations and craft-gilds
to be free, a struggle which, though it was to result in the
breaking up of the mediæval hierarchy, began by an
appearance of strengthening it by adding to its members,
increasing its power of production, and so making it more stable
for the time being.</p>
<p>About this struggle, and the kind of life which accompanied
it, I may have to write another time, and so will not say more
about it here. Except this, that it was much furthered by
the change that gradually took place between the landlords and
the class on whom all society rested, the serfs. These at
first were men who had no more rights than chattel slaves had,
except that mostly, as part of the stock of the manor, they could
not be sold off it; they had to do all the work of the manor, and
to earn their own livelihood off it as they best could. But
as the power of production increased, owing to better methods of
working, and as the country got to be more settled, their
task-work became easier of performance and their own land more
productive to them; and that tendency to the definition and
differentiation of rights, moreover, was at work for their
benefit, and the custom of the manor defined what their services
were, and they began to acquire rights. From that time they
ceased to be pure serfs, and began to tend towards becoming
tenants, at first paying purely and simply <i>service</i> for
their holdings, but gradually commuting that service for fines
and money payment—for rent, in short.</p>
<p>Towards the close of the fourteenth century, after the country
had been depopulated by the Black Death, and impoverished by the
long war, the feudal lords of these copyholders and tenants began
to regret the slackness with which their predecessors had
exploited their <i>property</i>, the serfs, and to consider that
under the new commercial light which had begun to dawn upon them
<i>they</i> could do it much better if they only had their
property a little more in hand; but it was too late, for their
property had acquired rights, and therewithal had got strange
visions into their heads of a time much better than that in which
they lived, when even those rights should be supplanted by a
condition of things in which the assertion of rights for any one
set of men should no longer be needed, since all men should be
free to enjoy the fruits of their own labour.</p>
<p>Of that came the great episode of the Peasants’ War, led
by men like Wat Tyler, Jack Straw, and John Ball, who indeed,
with those they led, suffered for daring to be before their time,
for the revolt was put down with cruelty worthy of an Irish
landlord or a sweating capitalist of the present day; but,
nevertheless, serfdom came to an end in England, if not because
of the revolt, yet because of the events that made it, and
thereby a death-wound was inflicted on the feudal system.</p>
<p>From that time onward the country, passing through the various
troubles of a new French war of Henry V.’s time, and the
War of the Roses, did not heed these faction fights much.</p>
<p>The workmen grew in prosperity, but also they began to rise
into a new class, and a class beneath them of mere labourers who
were not serfs began to form, and to lay the foundations of
capitalistic production.</p>
<p>England got carried into the rising current of commercialism,
and the rich men and landlords to turn their attention to the
production of profit instead of the production of livelihood; the
gild-less journeyman and the landless labourer slowly came into
existence; the landlord got rid of his tenants all he could,
turned tillage into pasture, and sweated the pastures to death in
his eagerness for wool, which for him meant money and the
breeding of money; till at last the place of the serf, which had
stood empty, as it were, during a certain transition period,
during which the non-capitalistic production was expanding up to
its utmost limit, was filled by the proletarian working for the
service of a master in a new fashion, a fashion which exploited
and (woe worth the while!) exploits him very much more completely
than the customs of the manor of the feudal period.</p>
<p>The life of the worker and the production of goods in this
transition period, when Feudal society was sickening for its end,
is a difficult and wide subject that requires separate treatment;
at present I will leave the mediæval workman at the full
development of that period which found him a serf bound to the
manor, and which left him generally a yeoman or an artisan
sharing the collective <i>status</i> of his gild.</p>
<p>The workman of to-day, if he could realize the position of his
forerunner, has some reason to envy him: the feudal serf worked
hard, and lived poorly, and produced a rough livelihood for his
master; whereas the modern workman, working harder still, and
living little if any better than the serf, produces for his
master a state of luxury of which the old lord of the manor never
dreamed. The workman’s powers of production are
multiplied a thousandfold; his own livelihood remains pretty much
where it was. The balance goes to his master and the crowd
of useless, draggled-tailed knaves and fools who pander to his
idiotic sham desires, and who, under the pretentious title of the
intellectual part of the middle classes, have in their turn taken
the place of the mediæval jester.</p>
<p>Truly, if the Positivist motto, “Live for others,”
be taken in stark literality, the modern workman should be a good
and wise man, since he has no chance of living for himself!</p>
<p>And yet, I wish he were wiser still; wise enough to make an
end of the preaching of “Live on others,” which is
the motto set forth by commercialism to her favoured
children.</p>
<p>Yet in one thing the modern proletarian has an advantage over
the mediæval serf, and that advantage is a world in
itself. Many a century lay between the serf and successful
revolt, and though he tried it many a time and never lost heart,
yet the coming change which his martyrdom helped on was not to be
for him yet, but for the new masters of his successors.
With us it is different. A few years of wearisome struggle
against apathy and ignorance; a year or two of growing
hope—and then who knows? Perhaps a few months, or
perhaps a few days of the open struggle against brute force, with
the mask off its face, and the sword in its hand, and then we are
over the bar.</p>
<p>Who knows, I say? Yet this we know, that ahead of us,
with nothing betwixt us except such incidents as are necessary to
its development, lies the inevitable social revolution, which
will bring about the end of mastery and the triumph of
fellowship.</p>
<h2><SPAN name="page84"></SPAN><span class="pagenum"></span>THE HOPES OF CIVILIZATION.</h2>
<p><span class="smcap">Every</span> age has had its hopes, hopes
that look to something beyond the life of the age itself, hopes
that try to pierce into the future; and, strange to say, I
believe that those hopes have been stronger not in the heyday of
the epoch which has given them birth, but rather in its decadence
and times of corruption: in sober truth it may well be that these
hopes are but a reflection in those that live happily and
comfortably of the vain longings of those others who suffer with
little power of expressing their sufferings in an audible voice:
when all goes well the happy world forgets these people and their
desires, sure as it is that their woes are not dangerous to them
the wealthy: whereas when the woes and grief of the poor begin to
rise to a point beyond the endurance of men, fear conscious or
unconscious falls upon the rich, and they begin to look about
them to see what there may be among the elements of their society
which may be used as palliatives for the misery which, long
existing and ever growing greater among the slaves of that
society, is now at last forcing itself on the attention of the
masters. Times of change, disruption, and revolution are
naturally times of hope also, and not seldom the hopes of
something better to come are the first tokens that tell people
that revolution is at hand, though commonly such tokens are no
more believed than Cassandra’s prophecies, or are even
taken in a contrary sense by those who have anything to lose;
since they look upon them as signs of the prosperity of the
times, and the long endurance of that state of things which is so
kind to them. Let us then see what the hopes of
civilization are like to-day: for indeed I purpose speaking of
our own times chiefly, and will leave for the present all mention
of that older civilization which was destroyed by the healthy
barbarism out of which our present society has grown.</p>
<p>Yet a few words may be necessary concerning the birth of our
present epoch and the hopes it gave rise to, and what has become
of them: that will not take us very far back in history; as to my
mind our modern civilization begins with the stirring period
about the time of the Reformation in England, the time which in
the then more important countries of the Continent is known as
the period of the Renaissance, the so-called new-birth of art and
learning.</p>
<p>And first remember that this period includes the death-throes
of feudalism, with all the good and evil which that system bore
with it. For centuries past its end was getting ready by
the gradual weakening of the bonds of the great hierarchy which
held men together: the characteristics of those bonds were,
theoretically at least, personal rights and personal duties
between superior and inferior all down the scale; each man was
born, so to say, subject to these conditions, and the mere
accidents of his life could not free him from them: commerce, in
our sense of the word, there was none; capitalistic manufacture,
capitalistic exchange was unknown: to buy goods cheap that you
might sell them dear was a legal offence (forestalling): to buy
goods in the market in the morning and to sell them in the
afternoon in the same place was not thought a useful occupation
and was forbidden under the name of regrating; usury, instead of
leading as now directly to the highest offices of the State, was
thought wrong, and the profit of it mostly fell to the chosen
people of God: the robbery of the workers, thought necessary then
as now to the very existence of the State, was carried out quite
crudely without any concealment or excuse by arbitrary taxation
or open violence: on the other hand, life was easy, and common
necessaries plenteous; the holidays of the Church were holidays
in the modern sense of the word, downright play-days, and there
were ninety-six obligatory ones: nor were the people tame and
sheep-like, but as rough-handed and bold a set of good fellows as
ever rubbed through life under the sun.</p>
<p>I remember three passages, from contemporary history or
gossip, about the life of those times which luck has left us, and
which illustrate curiously the change that has taken place in the
habits of Englishmen. A lady writing from Norfolk 400 years
ago to her husband in London, amidst various commissions for
tapestries, groceries, and gowns, bids him also not to forget to
bring back with him a good supply of cross-bows and bolts, since
the windows of their hall were too low to be handy for long-bow
shooting. A German traveller, writing quite at the end of
the mediæval period, speaks of the English as the laziest
and proudest people and the best cooks in Europe. A Spanish
ambassador about the same period says, “These English live
in houses built of sticks and mud, <SPAN name="citation87"></SPAN><SPAN href="#footnote87" class="citation">[87]</SPAN> but therein they
fare as plenteously as lords.”</p>
<p>Indeed, I confess that it is with a strange emotion that I
recall these times and try to realize the life of our
forefathers, men who were named like ourselves, spoke nearly the
same tongue, lived on the same spots of earth, and therewithal
were as different from us in manners, habits, ways of life and
thought, as though they lived in another planet. The very
face of the country has changed; not merely I mean in London and
the great manufacturing centres, but through the country
generally; there is no piece of English ground, except such
places as Salisbury Plain, but bears witness to the amazing
change which 400 years has brought upon us.</p>
<p>Not seldom I please myself with trying to realize the face of
mediæval England; the many chases and great woods, the
stretches of common tillage and common pasture quite unenclosed;
the rough husbandry of the tilled parts, the unimproved breeds of
cattle, sheep, and swine; especially the latter, so lank and long
and lathy, looking so strange to us; the strings of packhorses
along the bridle-roads, the scantiness of the wheel-roads, scarce
any except those left by the Romans, and those made from
monastery to monastery: the scarcity of bridges, and people using
ferries instead, or fords where they could; the little towns,
well bechurched, often walled; the villages just where they are
now (except for those that have nothing but the church left to
tell of them), but better and more populous; their churches, some
big and handsome, some small and curious, but all crowded with
altars and furniture, and gay with pictures and ornament; the
many religious houses, with their glorious architecture; the
beautiful manor-houses, some of them castles once, and survivals
from an earlier period; some new and elegant; some out of all
proportion small for the importance of their lords. How
strange it would be to us if we could be landed in fourteenth
century England; unless we saw the crest of some familiar hill,
like that which yet bears upon it a symbol of an English tribe,
and from which, looking down on the plain where Alfred was born,
I once had many such ponderings, we should not know into what
country of the world we were come: the name is left, scarce a
thing else.</p>
<p>And when I think of this it quickens my hope of what may be:
even so it will be with us in time to come; all will have
changed, and another people will be dwelling here in England,
who, although they may be of our blood and bear our name, will
wonder how we lived in the nineteenth century.</p>
<p>Well, under all that rigidly ordered caste society of the
fourteenth century, with its rough plenty, its sauntering life,
its cool acceptance of rudeness and violence, there was going on
a keen struggle of classes which carried with it the hope of
progress of those days: the serfs gradually getting freed, and
becoming some of them the town population, the first journeymen,
or “free-labourers,” so called, some of them the
copyholders of agricultural land: the corporations of the towns
gathered power, the craft-gilds grew into perfection and
corruption, the power of the Crown increased, attended with
nascent bureaucracy; in short, the middle class was forming
underneath the outward show of feudalism still intact: and all
was getting ready for the beginning of the great commercial epoch
in whose <i>latter</i> days I would fain hope we are
living. That epoch began with the portentous change of
agriculture which meant cultivating for profit instead of for
livelihood, and which carried with it the expropriation of the
<i>people</i> from the land, the extinction of the yeoman, and
the rise of the capitalist farmer; and the growth of the town
population, which, swelled by the drift of the landless vagabonds
and masterless men, grew into a definite proletariat or class of
free-workmen; and their existence made that of the embryo
capitalist-manufacturer also possible; and the reign of
commercial contract and cash payment began to take the place of
the old feudal hierarchy, with its many-linked chain of personal
responsibilities. The latter half of the seventeenth
century, the reign of Charles II., saw the last blow struck at
this feudal system, when the landowners’ military service
was abolished, and they became simple owners of property that had
no duties attached to it save the payment of a land-tax.</p>
<p>The hopes of the early part of the commercial period may be
read in almost every book of the time, expressed in various
degrees of dull or amusing pedantry, and show a naïf
arrogance and contempt of the times just past through which
nothing but the utmost simplicity of ignorance could have
attained to. But the times were stirring, and gave birth to
the most powerful individualities in many branches of literature,
and More and Campanella, at least from the midst of the exuberant
triumph of young commercialism, gave to the world prophetic hopes
of times yet to come when that commercialism itself should have
given place to the society which we hope will be the next
transform of civilization into something else; into a new social
life.</p>
<p>This period of early and exuberant hopes passed into the next
stage of sober realization of many of them, for commerce grew and
grew, and moulded all society to its needs: the workman of the
sixteenth century worked still as an individual with little
co-operation, and scarce any division of labour: by the end of
the seventeenth he had become only a part of a group which by
that time was in the handicrafts the real unit of production;
division of labour even at that period had quite destroyed his
individuality, and the worker was but part of a machine: all
through the eighteenth century this system went on progressing
towards perfection, till to most men of that period, to most of
those who were in any way capable of expressing their thoughts,
civilization had already reached a high stage of perfection, and
was certain to go on from better to better.</p>
<p>These hopes were not on the surface of a very revolutionary
kind, but nevertheless the class struggle still went on, and
quite openly too; for the remains of feudality, aided by the mere
mask and grimace of the religion, which was once a real part of
the feudal system, hampered the progress of commerce sorely, and
seemed a thousandfold more powerful than it really was; because
in spite of the class struggle there was really a covert alliance
between the powerful middle classes who were the children of
commerce and their old masters the aristocracy; an unconscious
understanding between them rather, in the midst of their contest,
that certain matters were to be respected even by the advanced
party: the contest and civil war between the king and the commons
in England in the seventeenth century illustrates this well: the
caution with which privilege was attacked in the beginning of the
struggle, the unwillingness of all the leaders save a few
enthusiasts to carry matters to their logical consequences, even
when the march of events had developed the antagonism between
aristocratic privilege and middle-class freedom of contract (so
called); finally, the crystallization of the new order conquered
by the sword of Naseby into a mongrel condition of things between
privilege and bourgeois freedom, the defeat and grief of the
purist Republicans, and the horror at and swift extinction of the
Levellers, the pioneers of Socialism in that day, all point to
the fact that the “party of progress,” as we should
call it now, was determined after all that privilege should not
be abolished further than its own standpoint.</p>
<p>The seventeenth century ended in the great Whig revolution in
England, and, as I said, commerce throve and grew enormously, and
the power of the middle classes increased proportionately and all
things seemed going smoothly with them, till at last in France
the culminating corruption of a society, still nominally existing
for the benefit of the privileged aristocracy, forced their hand:
the old order of things, backed as it was by the power of the
executive, by that semblance of overwhelming physical force which
is the real and only cement of a society founded on the slavery
of the many—the aristocratic power, seemed strong and
almost inexpugnable: and since any stick will do to beat a dog
with, the middle classes in France were forced to take up the
first stick that lay ready to hand if they were not to give way
to the aristocrats, which indeed the whole evolution of history
forbade them to do. Therefore, as in England in the
seventeenth century, the middle classes allied themselves to
religious and republican, and even communistic enthusiasts, with
the intention, firm though unexpressed, to keep them down when
they had mounted to power by their means, so in France they had
to ally themselves with the proletariat; which, shamefully
oppressed and degraded as it had been, now for the first time in
history began to feel its power, the power of numbers: by means
of this help they triumphed over aristocratic privilege, but, on
the other hand, although the proletariat was speedily reduced
again to a position not much better than that it had held before
the revolution, the part it played therein gave a new and
terrible character to that revolution, and from that time forward
the class struggle entered on to a new phase; the middle classes
had gained a complete victory, which in France carried with it
all the outward signs of victory, though in England they chose to
consider a certain part of themselves an aristocracy, who had
indeed little signs of aristocracy about them either for good or
for evil, being in very few cases of long descent, and being in
their manners and ideas unmistakably <i>bourgeois</i>.</p>
<p>So was accomplished the second act of the great class struggle
with whose first act began the age of commerce; as to the hopes
of this period of the revolution we all know how extravagant they
were; what a complete regeneration of the world was expected to
result from the abolition of the grossest form of privilege; and
I must say that, before we mock at the extravagance of those
hopes, we should try to put ourselves in the place of those that
held them, and try to conceive how the privilege of the old
noblesse must have galled the respectable well-to-do people of
that time. Well, the reasonable part of those hopes were
realized by the revolution; in other words, it accomplished what
it really aimed at, the freeing of commerce from the fetters of
sham feudality; or, in other words, the destruction of
aristocratic privilege. The more extravagant part of the
hopes expressed by the eighteenth century revolution were vague
enough, and tended in the direction of supposing that the working
classes would be benefited by what was to the interest of the
middle class in some way quite unexplained—by a kind of
magic, one may say—which welfare of the workers, as it was
never directly aimed at, but only hoped for by the way, so also
did not come about by any such magical means, and the triumphant
middle classes began gradually to find themselves looked upon no
longer as rebellious servants, but as oppressive masters.</p>
<p>The middle class had freed commerce from her fetters of
privilege, and had freed thought from her fetters of theology, at
least partially; but it had not freed, nor attempted to free,
labour from its fetters. The leaders of the French
Revolution, even amidst the fears, suspicions and slaughter of
the Terror, upheld the rights of “property” so
called, though a new pioneer or prophet appeared in France,
analogous in some respects to the Levellers of Cromwell’s
time, but, as might be expected, far more advanced and reasonable
than they were. Gracchus Babeuf and his fellows were
treated as criminals, and died or suffered the torture of prison
for attempting to put into practice those words which the
Republic still carried on its banners, and Liberty, Fraternity,
and Equality were interpreted in a middle-class, or if you please
a Jesuitical, sense, as the rewards of success for those who
could struggle into an exclusive class; and at last property had
to be defended by a military adventurer, and the Revolution
seemed to have ended with Napoleonism.</p>
<p>Nevertheless, the Revolution was not dead, nor was it possible
to say thus far and no further to the rising tide.
Commerce, which had created the propertyless proletariat
throughout civilization had still another part to play, which is
not yet played out; she had and has to teach the workers to know
what they are; to educate them, to consolidate them, and not only
to give them aspirations for their advancement as a class, but to
make means for them to realize those aspirations. All this
she did, nor loitered in her work either; from the beginning of
the nineteenth century the history of civilization is really the
history of the last of the class-struggles which was inaugurated
by the French Revolution; and England, who all through the times
of the Revolution and the Cæsarism which followed it
appeared to be the steady foe of Revolution, was really as
steadily furthering it; her natural conditions, her store of coal
and minerals, her temperate climate, extensive sea-board and many
harbours, and lastly her position as the outpost of Europe
looking into America across the ocean, doomed her to be for a
time at least the mistress of the commerce of the civilized
world, and its agent with barbarous and semi-barbarous
countries. The necessities of this destiny drove her into
the implacable war with France, a war which, nominally waged on
behalf of monarchical principles, was really, though doubtless
unconsciously, carried on for the possession of the foreign and
colonial markets. She came out victorious from that war,
and fully prepared to take advantage of the industrial revolution
which had been going on the while, and which I now ask you to
note.</p>
<p>I have said that the eighteenth century perfected the system
of labour which took the place of the mediæval system,
under which a workman individually carried his piece of work all
through its various stages from the first to the last.</p>
<p>This new system, the first change in industrial production
since the Middle Ages, is known as the system of division of
labour, wherein, as I said, the unit of labour is a group, not a
man; the individual workman in this system is kept life-long at
the performance of some task quite petty in itself, and which he
soon masters, and having mastered it has nothing more to do but
to go on increasing his speed of hand under the spur of
competition with his fellows, until he has become the perfect
machine which it is his ultimate duty to become, since without
attaining to that end he must die or become a pauper. You
can well imagine how this glorious invention of division of
labour, this complete destruction of individuality in the
workman, and his apparent hopeless enslavement to his
profit-grinding master, stimulated the hopes of civilization;
probably more hymns have been sung in praise of division of
labour, more sermons preached about it, than have done homage to
the precept, “do unto others as ye would they should do
unto you.”</p>
<p>To drop all irony, surely this was one of those stages of
civilization at which one might well say that, if it was to stop
there, it was a pity that it had ever got so far. I have
had to study books and methods of work of the eighteenth century
a good deal, French chiefly; and I must say that the impression
made on me by that study is that the eighteenth century artisan
must have been a terrible product of civilization, and quite in a
condition to give rise to <i>hopes</i>—of the torch, the
pike, and the guillotine.</p>
<p>However, civilization was not going to stop there; having
turned the man into a machine, the next stage for commerce to aim
at was to contrive machines which would widely dispense with
human labour; nor was this aim altogether disappointed.</p>
<p>Now, at first sight it would seem that having got the workman
into such a plight as he was, as the slave of division of labour,
this new invention of machines which should free him from a part
of his labour at least, could be nothing to him but an unmixed
blessing. Doubtless it will prove to have been so in the
end, when certain institutions have been swept away which most
people now look on as eternal; but a longish time has passed
during which the workman’s hopes of civilization have been
disappointed, for those who invented the machines, or rather who
profited by their invention, did not aim at the saving of labour
in the sense of reducing the labour which each man had to do,
but, first taking it for granted that every workman would have to
work as long as he could stand up to it, aimed, under those
conditions of labour, at producing the utmost possible amount of
goods which they could sell at a profit.</p>
<p>Need I dwell on the fact that, under these circumstances, the
invention of the machines has benefited the workman but little
even to this day?</p>
<p>Nay, at first they made his position worse than it had been:
for, being thrust on the world very suddenly, they distinctly
brought about an industrial revolution, changing everything
suddenly and completely; industrial productiveness was increased
prodigiously, but so far from the workers reaping the benefit of
this, they were thrown out of work in enormous numbers, while
those who were still employed were reduced from the position of
skilled artisans to that of unskilled labourers: the aims of
their masters being, as I said, to make a profit, they did not
trouble themselves about this as a class, but took it for granted
that it was something that couldn’t be helped and
didn’t hurt <i>them</i>; nor did they think of offering to
the workers that compensation for harassed interests which they
have since made a point of claiming so loudly for themselves.</p>
<p>This was the state of things which followed on the conclusion
of European peace, and even that peace itself rather made matters
worse than better, by the sudden cessation of all war industries,
and the throwing on to the market many thousands of soldiers and
sailors: in short, at no period of English history was the
condition of the workers worse than in the early years of the
nineteenth century.</p>
<p>There seem during this period to have been two currents of
hope that had reference to the working classes: the first
affected the masters, the second the men.</p>
<p>In England, and, in what I am saying of this period, I am
chiefly thinking of England, the hopes of the richer classes ran
high; and no wonder; for England had by this time become the
mistress of the markets of the world, and also, as the people of
that period were never weary of boasting, the workshop of the
world: the increase in the riches of the country was enormous,
even at the early period I am thinking of now—prior to
’48, I mean—though it increased much more speedily in
times that we have all seen: but part of the jubilant hopes of
this newly rich man concerned his servants, the instruments of
his fortune: it was hoped that the population in general would
grow wiser, better educated, thriftier, more industrious, more
comfortable; for which hope there was surely some foundation,
since man’s mastery over the forces of Nature was growing
yearly towards completion; but you see these benevolent gentlemen
supposed that these hopes would be realized perhaps by some
unexplained magic as aforesaid, or perhaps by the
working-classes, <i>at their own expense</i>, by the exercise of
virtues supposed to be specially suited to their condition, and
called, by their masters, “thrift” and
“industry.” For this latter supposition there
was no foundation: indeed, the poor wretches who were thrown out
of work by the triumphant march of commerce had perforce worn
thrift threadbare, and could hardly better their exploits in
<i>that</i> direction; while as to those who worked in the
factories, or who formed the fringe of labour elsewhere, industry
was no new gospel to them, since they already worked as long as
they could work without dying at the loom, the spindle, or the
stithy. They for their part had their hopes, vague enough
as to their ultimate aim, but expressed in the passing day by a
very obvious tendency to revolt: this tendency took various
forms, which I cannot dwell on here, but settled down at last
into Chartism: about which I must speak a few words: but first I
must mention, I can scarce do more, the honoured name of Robert
Owen, as representative of the nobler hopes of his day, just as
More was of his, and the lifter of the torch of Socialism amidst
the dark days of the confusion consequent on the reckless greed
of the early period of the great factory industries.</p>
<p>That the conditions under which man lived could affect his
life and his deeds infinitely, that not selfish greed and
ceaseless contention, but brotherhood and co-operation were the
bases of true society, was the gospel which he preached and also
practised with a single-heartedness, devotion, and fervour of
hope which have never been surpassed: he was the embodied hope of
the days when the advance of knowledge and the sufferings of the
people thrust revolutionary hope upon those thinkers who were not
in some form or other in the pay of the sordid masters of
society.</p>
<p>As to the Chartist agitation, there is this to be said of it,
that it was thoroughly a working-class movement, and it was
caused by the simplest and most powerful of all
causes—hunger. It is noteworthy that it was
strongest, especially in its earlier days, in the Northern and
Midland manufacturing districts—that is, in the places
which felt the distress caused by the industrial revolution most
sorely and directly; it sprang up with particular vigour in the
years immediately following the great Reform Bill; and it has
been remarked that disappointment of the hopes which that measure
had cherished had something to do with its bitterness. As
it went on, obvious causes for failure were developed in it;
self-seeking leadership; futile discussion of the means of making
the change, before organization of the party was perfected; blind
fear of ultimate consequences on the part of some, blind
disregard to immediate consequences on the part of others; these
were the surface reasons for its failure: but it would have
triumphed over all these and accomplished revolution in England,
if it had not been for causes deeper and more vital than
these. Chartism differed from mere Radicalism in being a
class movement; but its aim was after all political rather than
social. The Socialism of Robert Owen fell short of its
object because it did not understand that, as long as there is a
privileged class in possession of the executive power, they will
take good care that their economical position, which enables them
to live on the unpaid labour of the people, is not tampered with:
the hopes of the Chartists were disappointed because they did not
understand that true political freedom is impossible to people
who are economically enslaved: there is no first and second in
these matters, the two must go hand in hand together: we cannot
live as we will, and as we should, as long as we allow people to
<i>govern</i> us whose interest it is that we should live as
<i>they</i> will, and by no means as we should; neither is it any
use claiming the right to manage our own business unless we are
prepared to have some business of our own: these two aims united
mean the furthering of the class struggle till all classes are
abolished—the divorce of one from the other is fatal to any
hope of social advancement.</p>
<p>Chartism therefore, though a genuine popular movement, was
incomplete in its aims and knowledge; the time was not yet come
and it could not triumph openly; but it would be a mistake to say
that it failed utterly: at least it kept alive the holy flame of
discontent; it made it possible for us to attain to the political
goal of democracy, and thereby to advance the cause of the people
by the gain of a stage from whence could be seen the fresh gain
to be aimed at.</p>
<p>I have said that the time for revolution had not then come:
the great wave of commercial success went on swelling, and though
the capitalists would if they had dared have engrossed the whole
of the advantages thereby gained at the expense of their wage
slaves, the Chartist revolt warned them that it was not safe to
attempt it. They were <i>forced</i> to try to allay
discontent by palliative measures. They had to allow
Factory Acts to be passed regulating the hours and conditions of
labour of women and children, and consequently of men also in
some of the more important and consolidated industries; they were
<i>forced</i> to repeal the ferocious laws against combination
among the workmen; so that the Trades Unions won for themselves a
legal position and became a power in the labour question, and
were able by means of strikes and threats of strikes to regulate
the wages granted to the workers, and to raise the standard of
livelihood for a certain part of the skilled workmen and the
labourers associated with them: though the main part of the
unskilled, including the agricultural workmen, were no better off
than before.</p>
<p>Thus was damped down the flame of a discontent vague in its
aims, and passionately crying out for what, if granted, it could
not have used: twenty years ago any one hinting at the
possibility of serious class discontent in this country would
have been looked upon as a madman; in fact, the well-to-do and
cultivated were quite unconscious (as many still are) that there
was any class distinction in this country other than what was
made by the rags and cast clothes of feudalism, which in a
perfunctory manner they still attacked.</p>
<p>There was no sign of revolutionary feeling in England twenty
years ago: the middle class were so rich that they had no need to
hope for anything—but a heaven which they did not believe
in: the well-to-do working men did not hope, since they were not
pinched and had no means of learning their degraded position: and
lastly, the drudges of the proletariat had such hope as charity,
the hospital, the workhouse, and kind death at last could offer
them.</p>
<p>In this stock-jobbers’ heaven let us leave our dear
countrymen for a little, while I say a few words about the
affairs of the people on the continent of Europe. Things
were not quite so smooth for the fleecer there: Socialist
thinkers and writers had arisen about the same time as Robert
Owen; St. Simon, Proudhon, Fourier and his followers kept up the
traditions of hope in the midst of a <i>bourgeois</i>
world. Amongst these Fourier is the one that calls for most
attention: since his doctrine of the necessity and possibility of
making labour attractive is one which Socialism can by no means
do without. France also kept up the revolutionary and
insurrectionary tradition, the result of something like hope
still fermenting amongst the proletariat: she fell at last into
the clutches of a second Cæsarism developed by the basest
set of sharpers, swindlers, and harlots that ever insulted a
country, and of whom our own happy <i>bourgeois</i> at home made
heroes and heroines: the hideous open corruption of Parisian
society, to which, I repeat, our respectable classes accorded
heartfelt sympathy, was finally swept away by the horrors of a
race war: the defeats and disgraces of this war developed, on the
one hand, an increase in the wooden implacability and baseness of
the French <i>bourgeois</i>, but on the other made way for
revolutionary hope to spring again, from which resulted the
attempt to establish society on the basis of the freedom of
labour, which we call the Commune of Paris of 1871.
Whatever mistakes or imprudences were made in this attempt, and
all wars blossom thick with such mistakes, I will leave the
reactionary enemies of the people’s cause to put forward:
the immediate and obvious result was the slaughter of thousands
of brave and honest revolutionists at the hands of the
respectable classes, the loss in fact of an army for the popular
cause: but we may be sure that the results of the Commune will
not stop there: to all Socialists that heroic attempt will give
hope and ardour in the cause as long as it is to be won; we feel
as though the Paris workman had striven to bring the day-dawn for
us, and had lifted us the sun’s rim over the horizon, never
to set in utter darkness again: of such attempts one must say,
that though those who perished in them might have been put in a
better place in the battle, yet after all brave men never die for
nothing, when they die for principle.</p>
<p>Let us shift from France to Germany before we get back to
England again, and conclude with a few words about our hopes at
the present day. To Germany we owe the school of
economists, at whose head stands the name of Karl Marx, who have
made modern Socialism what it is: the earlier Socialist writers
and preachers based their hopes on man being taught to see the
desirableness of co-operation taking the place of competition,
and adopting the change voluntarily and consciously, and they
trusted to schemes more or less artificial being tried and
accepted, although such schemes were necessarily constructed out
of the materials which capitalistic society offered: but the new
school, starting with an historical view of what had been, and
seeing that a law of evolution swayed all events in it, was able
to point out to us that the evolution was still going on, and
that, whether Socialism be desirable or not, it is at least
inevitable. Here then was at last a hope of a different
kind to any that had gone before it; and the German and Austrian
workmen were not slow to learn the lesson founded on this theory;
from being one of the most backward countries in Europe in the
movement, before Lassalle started his German workman’s
party in 1863, Germany soon became the leader in it:
Bismarck’s repressive law has only acted on opinion there,
as the roller does to the growing grass—made it firmer and
stronger; and whatever vicissitudes may be the fate of the party
as a party, there can be no doubt that Socialistic opinion is
firmly established there, and that when the time is ripe for it
that opinion will express itself in action.</p>
<p>Now, in all I have been saying, I have been wanting you to
trace the fact that, ever since the establishment of
commercialism on the ruins of feudality, there has been growing a
steady feeling on the part of the workers that they are a class
dealt with as a class, and in like manner to deal with others;
and that as this class feeling has grown, so also has grown with
it a consciousness of the antagonism between their class and the
class which employs it, as the phrase goes; that is to say, which
lives by means of its labour.</p>
<p>Now it is just this growing consciousness of the fact that as
long as there exists in society a propertied class living on the
labour of a propertyless one, there <i>must</i> be a struggle
always going on between those two classes—it is just the
dawning knowledge of this fact which should show us what
civilization can hope for—namely, transformation into true
society, in which there will no longer be classes with their
necessary struggle for existence and superiority: for the
antagonism of classes which began in all simplicity between the
master and the chattel slave of ancient society, and was
continued between the feudal lord and the serf of mediæval
society, has gradually become the contention between the
capitalist developed from the workman of the last-named period,
and the wage-earner: in the former struggle the rise of the
artisan and villenage tenant created a new class, the middle
class, while the place of the old serf was filled by the
propertyless labourer, with whom the middle class, which has
absorbed the aristocracy, is now face to face: the struggle
between the classes therefore is once again a simple one, as in
the days of the classical peoples; but since there is no longer
any strong race left out of civilization, as in the time of the
disruption of Rome, the whole struggle in all its simplicity
between those who have and those who lack is <i>within</i>
civilization.</p>
<p>Moreover, the capitalist or modern slave-owner has been forced
by his very success, as we have seen, to organize his slaves, the
wage-earners, into a co-operation for production so well arranged
that it requires little but his own elimination to make it a
foundation for communal life: in the teeth also of the experience
of past ages, he has been compelled to allow a modicum of
education to the propertyless, and has not even been able to
deprive them wholly of political rights; his own advance in
wealth and power has bred for him the very enemy who is doomed to
make an end of him.</p>
<p>But will there be any new class to take the place of the
present proletariat when that has triumphed, as it must do, over
the present privileged class? We cannot foresee the future,
but we may fairly hope not: at least we cannot see any signs of
such a new class forming. It is impossible to see how
destruction of privilege can stop short of absolute equality of
condition; pure Communism is the logical deduction from the
imperfect form of the new society, which is generally
differentiated from it as Socialism.</p>
<p>Meantime, it is this simplicity and directness of the growing
contest which above all things presents itself as a terror to the
conservative instinct of the present day. Many among the
middle class who are sincerely grieved and shocked at the
condition of the proletariat which civilization has created, and
even alarmed by the frightful inequalities which it fosters, do
nevertheless shudder back from the idea of the class struggle,
and strive to shut their eyes to the fact that it is going
on. They try to think that peace is not only possible, but
natural, between the two classes, the very essence of whose
existence is that each can only thrive by what it manages to
force the other to yield to it. They propose to themselves
the impossible problem of raising the inferior or exploited
classes into a position in which they will cease to struggle
against the superior classes, while the latter will not cease to
exploit them. This absurd position drives them into the
concoction of schemes for bettering the condition of the working
classes at their own expense, some of them futile, some merely
fantastic; or they may be divided again into those which point
out the advantages and pleasures of involuntary asceticism, and
reactionary plans for importing the conditions of the production
and life of the Middle Ages (wholly misunderstood by them, by the
way) into the present system of the capitalist farmer, the great
industries, and the universal world-market. Some see a
solution of the social problem in sham co-operation, which is
merely an improved form of joint-stockery: others preach thrift
to (precarious) incomes of eighteen shillings a week, and
industry to men killing themselves by inches in working overtime,
or to men whom the labour-market has rejected as not wanted:
others beg the proletarians not to breed so fast; an injunction
the compliance with which might be at first of advantage to the
proletarians themselves in their present condition, but would
certainly undo the capitalists, if it were carried to any
lengths, and would lead through ruin and misery to the violent
outbreak of the very revolution which these timid people are so
anxious to forego.</p>
<p>Then there are others who, looking back on the past, and
perceiving that the workmen of the Middle Ages lived in more
comfort and self-respect than ours do, even though they were
subjected to the class rule of men who were looked on as another
order of beings than they, think that if those conditions of life
could be reproduced under our better political conditions the
question would be solved for a time at least. Their schemes
may be summed up in attempts, more or less preposterously futile,
to graft a class of independent peasants on our system of wages
and capital. They do not understand that this system of
independent workmen, producing almost entirely for the
consumption of themselves and their neighbours, and exploited by
the upper classes by obvious taxes on their labour, which was not
otherwise organized or interfered with by the exploiters, was
what in past times took the place of our system, in which the
workers sell their labour in the competitive market to masters
who have in their hands the whole organization of the markets,
and that these two systems are mutually destructive.</p>
<p>Others again believe in the possibility of starting from our
present workhouse system, for the raising of the lowest part of
the working population into a better condition, but do not
trouble themselves as to the position of the workers who are
fairly above the condition of pauperism, or consider what part
they will play in the contest for a better livelihood. And,
lastly, quite a large number of well-intentioned persons
belonging to the richer classes believe, that in a society that
compels competition for livelihood, and holds out to the workers
as a stimulus to exertion the hope of their rising into a
monopolist class of non-producers, it is yet possible to
“moralize” capital (to use a slang phrase of the
Positivists): that is to say, that a sentiment imported from a
religion which looks upon another world as the true sphere of
action for mankind, will override the necessities of our daily
life in this world. This curious hope is founded on the
feeling that a sentiment antagonistic to the full development of
commercialism exists and is gaining ground, and that this
sentiment is an independent growth of the ethics of the present
epoch. As a matter of fact, admitting its existence, as I
think we must do, it is the birth of the sense of insecurity
which is the shadow cast before by the approaching dissolution of
modern society founded on wage-slavery.</p>
<p>The greater part of these schemes aim, though seldom with the
consciousness of their promoters, at the creation of a new
middle-class out of the wage-earning class, and at their expense,
just as the present middle-class was developed out of the
serf-population of the early Middle Ages. It may be
possible that such a <i>further</i> development of the
middle-class lies before us, but it will not be brought about by
any such artificial means as the abovementioned schemes. If
it comes at all, it must be produced by events, which at present
we cannot foresee, acting on our commercial system, and
revivifying for a little time, maybe, that Capitalist Society
which now seems sickening towards its end.</p>
<p>For what is visible before us in these days is the competitive
commercial system killing itself by its own force: profits
lessening, businesses growing bigger and bigger, the small
employer of labour thrust out of his function, and the
aggregation of capital increasing the numbers of the lower
middle-class from above rather than from below, by driving the
smaller manufacturer into the position of a mere servant to the
bigger. The productivity of labour also increasing out of
all proportion to the capacity of the capitalists to manage the
market or deal with the labour supply: lack of employment
therefore becoming chronic, and discontent therewithal.</p>
<p>All this on the one hand. On the other, the workmen
claiming everywhere political equality, which cannot long be
denied; and education spreading, so that what between the
improvement in the education of the working-class and the
continued amazing fatuity of that of the upper classes, there is
a distinct tendency to equalization here; and, as I have hinted
above, all history shows us what a danger to society may be a
class at once educated and socially degraded: though, indeed, no
history has yet shown us—what is swiftly advancing upon
us—a class which, though it shall have attained knowledge,
shall lack utterly the refinement and self-respect which come
from the union of knowledge with leisure and ease of life.
The growth of such a class may well make the
“cultured” people of to-day tremble.</p>
<p>Whatever, therefore, of unforeseen and unconceived-of may lie
in the womb of the future, there is nothing visible before us but
a decaying system, with no outlook but ever-increasing
entanglement and blindness, and a new system, Socialism, the hope
of which is ever growing clearer in men’s minds—a
system which not only sees how labour can be freed from its
present fetters, and organized unwastefully, so as to produce the
greatest possible amount of wealth for the community and for
every member of it, but which bears with it its own ethics and
religion and æsthetics: that is the hope and promise of a
new and higher life in all ways. So that even if those
unforeseen economical events above spoken of were to happen, and
put off for a while the end of our Capitalist system, the latter
would drag itself along as an anomaly cursed by all, a mere clog
on the aspirations of humanity.</p>
<p>It is not likely that it will come to that: in all probability
the logical outcome of the latter days of Capitalism will go step
by step with its actual history: while all men, even its declared
enemies, will be working to bring Socialism about, the aims of
those who have learned to believe in the certainty and
beneficence of its advent will become clearer, their methods for
realizing it clearer also, and at last ready to hand. Then
will come that open acknowledgment for the necessity of the
change (an acknowledgment coming from the intelligence of
civilization) which is commonly called Revolution. It is no
use prophesying as to the events which will accompany that
revolution, but to a reasonable man it seems unlikely to the last
degree, or we will say impossible, that a moral sentiment will
induce the proprietary classes—those who live by
<i>owning</i> the means of production which the unprivileged
classes must needs <i>use</i>—to yield up this privilege
uncompelled; all one can hope is that they will see the implicit
threat of compulsion in the events of the day, and so yield with
a good grace to the terrible necessity of forming part of a world
in which all, including themselves, will work honestly and live
easily.</p>
<h2><SPAN name="page117"></SPAN><span class="pagenum"></span>THE AIMS OF ART.</h2>
<p><span class="smcap">In</span> considering the Aims of Art,
that is, why men toilsomely cherish and practise Art, I find
myself compelled to generalize from the only specimen of humanity
of which I know anything; to wit, myself. Now, when I think
of what it is that I desire, I find that I can give it no other
name than happiness. I want to be happy while I live; for
as for death, I find that, never having experienced it, I have no
conception of what it means, and so cannot even bring my mind to
bear upon it. I know what it is to live; I cannot even
guess what it is to be dead. Well, then, I want to be
happy, and even sometimes, say generally, to be merry; and I find
it difficult to believe that that is not the universal desire: so
that, whatever tends towards that end I cherish with all my best
endeavour. Now, when I consider my life further, I find
out, or seem to, that it is under the influence of two dominating
moods, which for lack of better words I must call the mood of
energy and the mood of idleness: these two moods are now one, now
the other, always crying out in me to be satisfied. When
the mood of energy is upon me, I must be doing something, or I
become mopish and unhappy; when the mood of idleness is on me, I
find it hard indeed if I cannot rest and let my mind wander over
the various pictures, pleasant or terrible, which my own
experience or my communing with the thoughts of other men, dead
or alive, have fashioned in it; and if circumstances will not
allow me to cultivate this mood of idleness, I find I must at the
best pass through a period of pain till I can manage to stimulate
my mood of energy to take its place and make me happy
again. And if I have no means wherewith to rouse up that
mood of energy to do its duty in making me happy, and I have to
toil while the idle mood is upon me, then am I unhappy indeed,
and almost wish myself dead, though I do not know what that
means.</p>
<p>Furthermore, I find that while in the mood of idleness memory
amuses me, in the mood of energy hope cheers me; which hope is
sometimes big and serious, and sometimes trivial, but that
without it there is no happy energy. Again, I find that
while I can sometimes satisfy this mood by merely exercising it
in work that has no result beyond the passing hour—in play,
in short—yet that it presently wearies of that and gets
languid, the hope therein being too trivial, and sometimes even
scarcely real; and that on the whole, to satisfy my master the
mood, I must either be making something or making believe to make
it.</p>
<p>Well, I believe that all men’s lives are compounded of
these two moods in various proportions, and that this explains
why they have always, with more or less of toil, cherished and
practised art.</p>
<p>Why should they have touched it else, and so added to the
labour which they could not choose but do in order to live?
It must have been done for their pleasure, since it has only been
in very elaborate civilizations that a man could get other men to
keep him alive merely to produce works of art, whereas all men
that have left any signs of their existence behind them have
practised art.</p>
<p>I suppose, indeed, that nobody will be inclined to deny that
the end proposed by a work of art is always to please the person
whose senses are to be made conscious of it. It was done
<i>for</i> some one who was to be made happier by it; his idle or
restful mood was to be amused by it, so that the vacancy which is
the besetting evil of that mood might give place to pleased
contemplation, dreaming, or what you will; and by this means he
would not so soon be driven into his workful or energetic mood:
he would have more enjoyment, and better.</p>
<p>The restraining of restlessness, therefore, is clearly one of
the essential aims of art, and few things could add to the
pleasure of life more than this. There are, to my
knowledge, gifted people now alive who have no other vice than
this of restlessness, and seemingly no other curse in their lives
to make them unhappy: but that is enough; it is “the little
rift within the lute.” Restlessness makes them
hapless men and bad citizens.</p>
<p>But granting, as I suppose you all will do, that this is a
most important function for art to fulfil, the question next
comes, at what price do we obtain it? I have admitted that
the practice of art has added to the labour of mankind, though I
believe in the long run it will not do so; but in adding to the
labour of man has it added, so far, to his pain? There
always have been people who would at once say yes to that
question; so that there have been and are two sets of people who
dislike and contemn art as an embarrassing folly. Besides
the pious ascetics, who look upon it as a worldly entanglement
which prevents men from keeping their minds fixed on the chances
of their individual happiness or misery in the next world; who,
in short, hate art, because they think that it adds to
man’s earthly happiness—besides these, there are also
people who, looking on the struggle of life from the most
reasonable point that they know of, contemn the arts because they
think that they add to man’s slavery by increasing the sum
of his painful labour: if this were the case, it would still, to
my mind, be a question whether it might not be worth the while to
endure the extra pain of labour for the sake of the extra
pleasure added to rest; assuming, for the present, equality of
condition among men. But it seems to me that it is not the
case that the practice of art adds to painful labour; nay more, I
believe that, if it did, art would never have arisen at all,
would certainly not be discernible, as it is, among peoples in
whom only the germs of civilization exist. In other words,
I believe that art cannot be the result of external compulsion;
the labour which goes to produce it is voluntary, and partly
undertaken for the sake of the labour itself, partly for the sake
of the hope of producing something which, when done, shall give
pleasure to the user of it. Or, again, this extra labour,
when it is extra, is undertaken with the aim of satisfying that
mood of energy by employing it to produce something worth doing,
and which, therefore, will keep before the worker a lively hope
while he is working; and also by giving it work to do in which
there is absolute immediate pleasure. Perhaps it is
difficult to explain to the non-artistic capacity that this
definite sensuous pleasure is always present in the handiwork of
the deft workman when he is working successfully, and that it
increases in proportion to the freedom and individuality of the
work. Also you must understand that this production of art,
and consequent pleasure in work, is not confined to the
production of matters which are works of art only, like pictures,
statues, and so forth, but has been and should be a part of all
labour in some form or other: so only will the claims of the mood
of energy be satisfied.</p>
<p>Therefore the Aim of Art is to increase the happiness of men,
by giving them beauty and interest of incident to amuse their
leisure, and prevent them wearying even of rest, and by giving
them hope and bodily pleasure in their work; or, shortly, to make
man’s work happy and his rest fruitful. Consequently,
genuine art is an unmixed blessing to the race of man.</p>
<p>But as the word “genuine” is a large
qualification, I must ask leave to attempt to draw some practical
conclusions from this assertion of the Aims of Art, which will, I
suppose, or indeed hope, lead us into some controversy on the
subject; because it is futile indeed to expect any one to speak
about art, except in the most superficial way, without
encountering those social problems which all serious men are
thinking of; since art is and must be, either in its abundance or
its barrenness, in its sincerity or its hollowness, the
expression of the society amongst which it exists.</p>
<p>First, then, it is clear to me that, at the present time,
those who look widest at things and deepest into them are quite
dissatisfied with the present state of the arts, as they are also
with the present condition of society. This I say in the
teeth of the supposed revivification of art which has taken place
of late years: in fact, that very excitement about the arts
amongst a part of the cultivated people of to-day does but show
on how firm a basis the dissatisfaction above mentioned
rests. Forty years ago there was much less talk about art,
much less practice of it, than there is now; and that is
specially true of the architectural arts, which I shall mostly
have to speak about now. People have consciously striven to
raise the dead in art since that time, and with some superficial
success. Nevertheless, in spite of this conscious effort, I
must tell you that England, to a person who can feel and
understand beauty, was a less grievous place to live in then than
it is now; and we who feel what art means know well, though we do
not often dare to say so, that forty years hence it will be a
more grievous place to us than it is now if we still follow up
the road we are on. Less than forty years ago—about
thirty—I first saw the city of Rouen, then still in its
outward aspect a piece of the Middle Ages: no words can tell you
how its mingled beauty, history, and romance took hold on me; I
can only say that, looking back on my past life, I find it was
the greatest pleasure I have ever had: and now it is a pleasure
which no one can ever have again: it is lost to the world for
ever. At that time I was an undergraduate of Oxford.
Though not so astounding, so romantic, or at first sight so
mediæval as the Norman city, Oxford in those days still
kept a great deal of its earlier loveliness: and the memory of
its grey streets as they then were has been an abiding influence
and pleasure in my life, and would be greater still if I could
only forget what they are now—a matter of far more
importance than the so-called learning of the place could have
been to me in any case, but which, as it was, no one tried to
teach me, and I did not try to learn. Since then the
guardians of this beauty and romance so fertile of education,
though professedly engaged in “the higher education”
(as the futile system of compromises which they follow is
nick-named), have ignored it utterly, have made its preservation
give way to the pressure of commercial exigencies, and are
determined apparently to destroy it altogether. There is
another pleasure for the world gone down the wind; here, again,
the beauty and romance have been uselessly, causelessly, most
foolishly thrown away.</p>
<p>These two cases are given simply because they have been fixed
in my mind; they are but types of what is going on everywhere
throughout civilization: the world is everywhere growing uglier
and more commonplace, in spite of the conscious and very
strenuous efforts of a small group of people towards the revival
of art, which are so obviously out of joint with the tendency of
the age that, while the uncultivated have not even heard of them,
the mass of the cultivated look upon them as a joke, and even
that they are now beginning to get tired of.</p>
<p>Now, if it be true, as I have asserted, that genuine art is an
unmixed blessing to the world, this is a serious matter; for at
first sight it seems to show that there will soon be no art at
all in the world, which will thus lose an unmixed blessing; it
can ill afford to do that, I think.</p>
<p>For art, if it has to die, has worn itself out, and its aim
will be a thing forgotten; and its aim was to make work happy and
rest fruitful. Is all work to be unhappy, all rest
unfruitful, then? Indeed, if art is to perish, that will be
the case, unless something is to take its place—something
at present unnamed, undreamed of.</p>
<p>I do not think that anything will take the place of art; not
that I doubt the ingenuity of man, which seems to be boundless in
the direction of making himself unhappy, but because I believe
the springs of art in the human mind to be deathless, and also
because it seems to me easy to see the causes of the present
obliteration of the arts.</p>
<p>For we civilized people have not given them up consciously, or
of our free will; we have been <i>forced</i> to give them
up. Perhaps I can illustrate that by the detail of the
application of machinery to the production of things in which
artistic form of some sort is possible. Why does a
reasonable man use a machine? Surely to save his
labour. There are some things which a machine can do as
well as a man’s hand, <i>plus</i> a tool, can do
them. He need not, for instance, grind his corn in a
hand-quern; a little trickle of water, a wheel, and a few simple
contrivances will do it all perfectly well, and leave him free to
smoke his pipe and think, or to carve the handle of his
knife. That, so far, is unmixed gain in the use of a
machine—always, mind you, supposing equality of condition
among men; no art is lost, leisure or time for more pleasurable
work is gained. Perhaps a perfectly reasonable and free man
would stop there in his dealings with machinery; but such reason
and freedom are too much to expect, so let us follow our
machine-inventor a step farther. He has to weave plain
cloth, and finds doing so dullish on the one hand, and on the
other that a power-loom will weave the cloth nearly as well as a
hand-loom: so, in order to gain more leisure or time for more
pleasurable work, he uses a power-loom, and foregoes the small
advantage of the little extra art in the cloth. But so
doing, as far as the art is concerned, he has not got a pure
gain; he has made a bargain between art and labour, and got a
makeshift as a consequence. I do not say that he may not be
right in so doing, but that he has lost as well as gained.
Now, this is as far as a man who values art and is reasonable
would go in the matter of machinery <i>as long as he was
free</i>—that is, was not <i>forced</i> to work for another
man’s profit; so long as he was living in a society <i>that
had accepted equality of condition</i>. Carry the machine
used for art a step farther, and he becomes an unreasonable man,
if he values art and is free. To avoid misunderstanding, I
must say that I am thinking of the modern machine, which is as it
were alive, and to which the man is auxiliary, and not of the old
machine, the improved tool, which is auxiliary to the man, and
only works as long as his hand is thinking; though I will remark,
that even this elementary form of machine has to be dropped when
we come to the higher and more intricate forms of art.
Well, as to the machine proper used for art, when it gets to the
stage above dealing with a necessary production that has
accidentally some beauty about it, a reasonable man with a
feeling for art will only use it when he is forced to. If
he thinks he would like ornament, for instance, and knows that
the machine cannot do it properly, and does not care to spend the
time to do it properly, why should he do it at all? He will
not diminish his leisure for the sake of making something he does
not want unless some man or band of men force him to it; so he
will either go without the ornament, or sacrifice some of his
leisure to have it genuine. That will be a sign that he
wants it very much, and that it will be worth his trouble: in
which case, again, his labour on it will not be mere trouble, but
will interest and please him by satisfying the needs of his mood
of energy.</p>
<p>This, I say, is how a reasonable man would act if he were free
from man’s compulsion; not being free, he acts very
differently. He has long passed the stage at which machines
are only used for doing work repulsive to an average man, or for
doing what could be as well done by a machine as a man, and he
instinctively expects a machine to be invented whenever any
product of industry becomes sought after. He is the slave
to machinery; the new machine <i>must</i> be invented, and when
invented he <i>must</i>—I will not say use it, but be used
by it, whether he likes it or not.</p>
<p>But why is he the slave to machinery? Because he is the
slave to the system for whose existence the invention of
machinery was necessary.</p>
<p>And now I must drop, or rather have dropped, the assumption of
the equality of condition, and remind you that, though in a sense
we are all the slaves of machinery, yet that some men are so
directly without any metaphor at all, and that these are just
those on whom the great body of the arts depends—the
workmen. It is necessary for the system which keeps them in
their position as an inferior class that they should either be
themselves machines or be the servants to machines, in no case
having any interest in the work which they turn out. To
their employers they are, so far as they are workmen, a part of
the machinery of the workshop or the factory; to themselves they
are proletarians, human beings working to live that they may live
to work: their part of craftsmen, of makers of things by their
own free will, is played out.</p>
<p>At the risk of being accused of sentimentality, I will say
that since this is so, since the work which produces the things
that should be matters of art is but a burden and a slavery, I
exult in this at least, that it cannot produce art; that all it
can do lies between stark utilitarianism and idiotic sham.</p>
<p>Or indeed is that merely sentimental? Rather, I think,
we who have learned to see the connection between industrial
slavery and the degradation of the arts have learned also to hope
for a future for those arts; since the day will certainly come
when men will shake off the yoke, and refuse to accept the mere
artificial compulsion of the gambling market to waste their lives
in ceaseless and hopeless toil; and when it does come, their
instincts for beauty and imagination set free along with them,
will produce such art as they need; and who can say that it will
not as far surpass the art of past ages as that does the poor
relics of it left us by the age of commerce?</p>
<p>A word or two on an objection which has often been made to me
when I have been talking on this subject. It may be said,
and is often, You regret the art of the Middle Ages (as indeed I
do), but those who produced it were not free; they were serfs, or
gild-craftsmen surrounded by brazen walls of trade restrictions;
they had no political rights, and were exploited by their
masters, the noble caste, most grievously. Well, I quite
admit that the oppression and violence of the Middle Ages had its
effect on the art of those days, its shortcomings are traceable
to them; they repressed art in certain directions, I do not doubt
that; and for that reason I say, that when we shake off the
present oppression as we shook off the old, we may expect the art
of the days of real freedom to rise above that of those old
violent days. But I do say that it was possible then to
have social, organic, hopeful progressive art; whereas now such
poor scraps of it as are left are the result of individual and
wasteful struggle, are retrospective and pessimistic. And
this hopeful art was possible amidst all the oppression of those
days, because the instruments of that oppression were grossly
obvious, and were external to the work of the craftsman.
They were laws and customs obviously intended to rob him, and
open violence of the highway-robbery kind. In short,
industrial production was not the instrument used for robbing the
“lower classes;” it is now the main instrument used
in that honourable profession. The mediæval craftsman
was free in his work, therefore he made it as amusing to himself
as he could; and it was his pleasure and not his pain that made
all things beautiful that were made, and lavished treasures of
human hope and thought on everything that man made, from a
cathedral to a porridge-pot. Come, let us put it in the way
least respectful to the mediæval craftsman, most polite to
the modern “hand:” the poor devil of the fourteenth
century, his work was of so little value that he was allowed to
waste it by the hour in pleasing himself—and others; but
our highly-strung mechanic, his minutes are too rich with the
burden of perpetual profit for him to be allowed to waste one of
them on art; the present system will not allow him—cannot
allow him—to produce works of art.</p>
<div class="gapspace"> </div>
<p>So that there has arisen this strange phenomenon, that there
is now a class of ladies and gentlemen, very refined indeed,
though not perhaps as well informed as is generally supposed, and
of this refined class there are many who do really love beauty
and incident—i.e., art, and would make sacrifices to get
it; and these are led by artists of great manual skill and high
intellect, forming altogether a large body of demand for the
article. And yet the supply does not come. Yes, and
moreover, this great body of enthusiastic demanders are no mere
poor and helpless people, ignorant fisher-peasants, half-mad
monks, scatter-brained sansculottes—none of those, in
short, the expression of whose needs has shaken the world so
often before, and will do yet again. No, they are of the
ruling classes, the masters of men, who can live without labour,
and have abundant leisure to scheme out the fulfilment of their
desires; and yet I say they cannot have the art which they so
much long for, though they hunt it about the world so hard,
sentimentalizing the sordid lives of the miserable peasants of
Italy and the starving proletarians of her towns, now that all
the picturesqueness has departed from the poor devils of our own
country-side, and of our own slums. Indeed, there is little
of reality left them anywhere, and that little is fast fading
away before the needs of the manufacturer and his ragged regiment
of workers, and before the enthusiasm of the archæological
restorer of the dead past. Soon there will be nothing left
except the lying dreams of history, the miserable wreckage of our
museums and picture-galleries, and the carefully guarded
interiors of our æsthetic drawing-rooms, unreal and
foolish, fitting witnesses of the life of corruption that goes on
there, so pinched and meagre and cowardly, with its concealment
and ignoring, rather than restraint of, natural longings; which
does not forbid the greedy indulgence in them if it can but be
decently hidden.</p>
<p>The art then is gone, and can no more be
“restored” on its old lines than a mediæval
building can be. The rich and refined cannot have it though
they would, and though we will believe many of them would.
And why? Because those who could give it to the rich are
not allowed by the rich to do so. In one word, slavery lies
between us and art.</p>
<p>I have said as much as that the aim of art was to destroy the
curse of labour by making work the pleasurable satisfaction of
our impulse towards energy, and giving to that energy hope of
producing something worth its exercise.</p>
<p>Now, therefore, I say, that since we cannot have art by
striving after its mere superficial manifestation, since we can
have nothing but its sham by so doing, there yet remains for us
to see how it would be if we let the shadow take care of itself
and try, if we can, to lay hold of the substance. For my
part I believe, that if we try to realize the aims of art without
much troubling ourselves what the aspect of the art itself shall
be, we shall find we shall have what we want at last: whether it
is to be called art or not, it will at least be <i>life</i>; and,
after all, that is what we want. It may lead us into new
splendours and beauties of visible art; to architecture with
manifolded magnificence free from the curious incompleteness and
failings of that which the older times have produced—to
painting, uniting to the beauty which mediæval art attained
the realism which modern art aims at; to sculpture, uniting the
beauty of the Greek and the expression of the Renaissance with
some third quality yet undiscovered, so as to give us the images
of men and women splendidly alive, yet not disqualified from
making, as all true sculpture should, architectural
ornament. All this it may do; or, on the other hand, it may
lead us into the desert, and art may seem to be dead amidst us;
or feebly and uncertainly to be struggling in a world which has
utterly forgotten its old glories.</p>
<p>For my part, with art as it now is, I cannot bring myself to
think that it much matters which of these dooms awaits it, so
long as each bears with it some hope of what is to come; since
here, as in other matters, there is no hope save in
Revolution. The old art is no longer fertile, no longer
yields us anything save elegantly poetical regrets; being barren,
it has but to die, and the matter of moment now is, as to how it
shall die, whether <i>with</i> hope or <i>without</i> it.</p>
<p>What is it, for instance, that has destroyed the Rouen, the
Oxford of <i>my</i> elegant poetic regret? Has it perished
for the benefit of the people, either slowly yielding to the
growth of intelligent change and new happiness? or has it been,
as it were, thunderstricken by the tragedy which mostly
accompanies some great new birth? Not so. Neither
phalangstere nor dynamite has swept its beauty away, its
destroyers have not been either the philanthropist or the
Socialist, the co-operator or the anarchist. It has been
sold, and at a cheap price indeed: muddled away by the greed and
incompetence of fools who do not know what life and pleasure
mean, who will neither take them themselves nor let others have
them. That is why the death of that beauty wounds us so: no
man of sense or feeling would dare to regret such losses if they
had been paid for by new life and happiness for the people.
But there is the people still as it was before, still facing for
its part the monster who destroyed all that beauty, and whose
name is Commercial Profit.</p>
<p>I repeat, that every scrap of genuine art will fall by the
same hands if the matter only goes on long enough, although a
sham art may be left in its place, which may very well be carried
on by <i>dilettanti</i> fine gentlemen and ladies without any
help from below; and, to speak plainly, I fear that this
gibbering ghost of the real thing would satisfy a great many of
those who now think themselves lovers of art; though it is not
difficult to see a long vista of its degradation till it shall
become at last a mere laughing-stock; that is to say, if the
thing were to go on: I mean, if art were to be for ever the
amusement of those whom we now call ladies and gentlemen.</p>
<p>But for my part I do not think it will go on long enough to
reach such depths as that; and yet I should be hypocritical if I
were to say that I thought that the change in the basis of
society, which would enfranchise labour and make men practically
equal in condition, would lead us by a short road to the splendid
new birth of art which I have mentioned, though I feel quite
certain that it would not leave what we now call art untouched,
since the aims of that revolution do include the aims of
art—viz., abolishing the curse of labour.</p>
<p>I suppose that this is what is likely to happen; that
machinery will go on developing, with the purpose of saving men
labour, till the mass of the people attain real leisure enough to
be able to appreciate the pleasure of life; till, in fact, they
have attained such mastery over Nature that they no longer fear
starvation as a penalty for not working more than enough.
When they get to that point they will doubtless turn themselves
and begin to find out what it is that they really want to
do. They would soon find out that the less work they did
(the less work unaccompanied by art, I mean), the more desirable
a dwelling-place the earth would be; they would accordingly do
less and less work, till the mood of energy, of which I began by
speaking, urged them on afresh: but by that time Nature, relieved
by the relaxation of man’s work, would be recovering her
ancient beauty, and be teaching men the old story of art.
And as the Artificial Famine, caused by men working for the
profit of a master, and which we now look upon as a matter of
course, would have long disappeared, they would be free to do as
they chose, and they would set aside their machines in all cases
where the work seemed pleasant or desirable for handiwork; till
in all crafts where production of beauty was required, the most
direct communication between a man’s hand and his brain
would be sought for. And there would be many occupations
also, as the processes of agriculture, in which the voluntary
exercise of energy would be thought so delightful, that people
would not dream of handing over its pleasure to the jaws of a
machine.</p>
<p>In short, men will find out that the men of our days were
wrong in first multiplying their needs, and then trying, each man
of them, to evade all participation in the means and processes
whereby those needs are satisfied; that this kind of division of
labour is really only a new and wilful form of arrogant and
slothful ignorance, far more injurious to the happiness and
contentment of life than the ignorance of the processes of
Nature, of what we sometimes call <i>science</i>, which men of
the earlier days unwittingly lived in.</p>
<p>They will discover, or rediscover rather, that the true secret
of happiness lies in the taking a genuine interest in all the
details of daily life, in elevating them by art instead of
handing the performance of them over to unregarded drudges, and
ignoring them; and that in cases where it was impossible either
so to elevate them and make them interesting, or to lighten them
by the use of machinery, so as to make the labour of them
trifling, that should be taken as a token that the supposed
advantages gained by them were not worth the trouble and had
better be given up. All this to my mind would be the
outcome of men throwing off the burden of Artificial Famine,
supposing, as I cannot help supposing, that the impulses which
have from the first glimmerings of history urged men on to the
practice of Art were still at work in them.</p>
<p>Thus and thus only <i>can</i> come about the new birth of Art,
and I think it <i>will</i> come about thus. You may say it
is a long process, and so it is; but I can conceive of a
longer. I have given you the Socialist or Optimist view of
the matter. Now for the Pessimist view.</p>
<p>I can conceive that the revolt against Artificial Famine or
Capitalism, which is now on foot, may be vanquished. The
result will be that the working class—the slaves of
society—will become more and more degraded; that they will
not strive against overwhelming force, but, stimulated by that
love of life which Nature, always anxious about the perpetuation
of the race, has implanted in us, will learn to bear
everything—starvation, overwork, dirt, ignorance,
brutality. All these things they will bear, as, alas! they
bear them too well even now; all this rather than risk sweet life
and bitter livelihood, and all sparks of hope and manliness will
die out of them.</p>
<p>Nor will their masters be much better off: the earth’s
surface will be hideous everywhere, save in the uninhabitable
desert; Art will utterly perish, as in the manual arts so in
literature, which will become, as it is indeed speedily becoming,
a mere string of orderly and calculated ineptitudes and
passionless ingenuities; Science will grow more and more
one-sided, more incomplete, more wordy and useless, till at last
she will pile herself up into such a mass of superstition, that
beside it the theologies of old time will seem mere reason and
enlightenment. All will get lower and lower, till the
heroic struggles of the past to realize hope from year to year,
from century to century, will be utterly forgotten, and man will
be an indescribable being—hopeless, desireless,
lifeless.</p>
<p>And will there be deliverance from this even? Maybe: man
may, after some terrible cataclysm, learn to strive towards a
healthy animalism, may grow from a tolerable animal into a
savage, from a savage into a barbarian, and so on; and some
thousands of years hence he may be beginning once more those arts
which we have now lost, and be carving interlacements like the
New Zealanders, or scratching forms of animals on their cleaned
blade-bones, like the pre-historic men of the drift.</p>
<p>But in any case, according to the pessimist view, which looks
upon revolt against Artificial Famine as impossible to succeed,
we shall wearily trudge the circle again, until some accident,
some unforeseen consequence of arrangement, makes an end of us
altogether.</p>
<p>That pessimism I do not believe in, nor, on the other hand, do
I suppose that it is altogether a matter of our wills as to
whether we shall further human progress or human degradation;
yet, since there are those who are impelled towards the Socialist
or Optimistic side of things, I must conclude that there is some
hope of its prevailing, that the strenuous efforts of many
individuals imply a force which is thrusting them on. So
that I believe that the “Aims of Art” will be
realized, though I know that they cannot be, so long as we groan
under the tyranny of Artificial Famine. Once again I warn
you against supposing, you who may specially love art, that you
will do any good by attempting to revivify art by dealing with
its dead exterior. I say it is the <i>aims of art</i> that
you must seek rather than the <i>art itself</i>; and in that
search we may find ourselves in a world blank and bare, as the
result of our caring at least this much for art, that we will not
endure the shams of it.</p>
<p>Anyhow, I ask you to think with me that the worst which can
happen to us is to endure tamely the evils that we see; that no
trouble or turmoil is so bad as that; that the necessary
destruction which reconstruction bears with it must be taken
calmly; that everywhere—in State, in Church, in the
household—we must be resolute to endure no tyranny, accept
no lie, quail before no fear, although they may come before us
disguised as piety, duty, or affection, as useful opportunity and
good-nature, as prudence or kindness. The world’s
roughness, falseness, and injustice will bring about their
natural consequences, and we and our lives are part of those
consequences; but since we inherit also the consequences of old
resistance to those curses, let us each look to it to have our
fair share of that inheritance also, which, if nothing else come
of it, will at least bring to us courage and hope; that is, eager
life while we live, which is above all things the Aim of Art.</p>
<h2><SPAN name="page141"></SPAN><span class="pagenum"></span>USEFUL WORK <span class="GutSmall"><i>VERSUS</i></span> USELESS TOIL.</h2>
<p><span class="smcap">The</span> above title may strike some of
my readers as strange. It is assumed by most people
nowadays that all work is useful, and by most well-to-to people
that all work is desirable. Most people, well-to-do or not,
believe that, even when a man is doing work which appears to be
useless, he is earning his livelihood by it—he is
“employed,” as the phrase goes; and most of those who
are well-to-do cheer on the happy worker with congratulations and
praises, if he is only “industrious” enough and
deprives himself of all pleasure and holidays in the sacred cause
of labour. In short, it has become an article of the creed
of modern morality that all labour is good in itself—a
convenient belief to those who live on the labour of
others. But as to those on whom they live, I recommend them
not to take it on trust, but to look into the matter a little
deeper.</p>
<p>Let us grant, first, that the race of man must either labour
or perish. Nature does not give us our livelihood gratis;
we must win it by toil of some sort or degree. Let us see,
then, if she does not give us some compensation for this
compulsion to labour, since certainly in other matters she takes
care to make the acts necessary to the continuance of life in the
individual and the race not only endurable, but even
pleasurable.</p>
<p>You may be sure that she does so, that it is of the nature of
man, when he is not diseased, to take pleasure in his work under
certain conditions. And, yet, we must say in the teeth of
the hypocritical praise of all labour, whatsoever it may be, of
which I have made mention, that there is some labour which is so
far from being a blessing that it is a curse; that it would be
better for the community and for the worker if the latter were to
fold his hands and refuse to work, and either die or let us pack
him off to the workhouse or prison—which you will.</p>
<p>Here, you see, are two kinds of work—one good, the other
bad; one not far removed from a blessing, a lightening of life;
the other a mere curse, a burden to life.</p>
<p>What is the difference between them, then? This: one has
hope in it, the other has not. It is manly to do the one
kind of work, and manly also to refuse to do the other.</p>
<p>What is the nature of the hope which, when it is present in
work, makes it worth doing?</p>
<p>It is threefold, I think—hope of rest, hope of product,
hope of pleasure in the work itself; and hope of these also in
some abundance and of good quality; rest enough and good enough
to be worth having; product worth having by one who is neither a
fool nor an ascetic; pleasure enough for all for us to be
conscious of it while we are at work; not a mere habit, the loss
of which we shall feel as a fidgety man feels the loss of the bit
of string he fidgets with.</p>
<p>I have put the hope of rest first because it is the simplest
and most natural part of our hope. Whatever pleasure there
is in some work, there is certainly some pain in all work, the
beast-like pain of stirring up our slumbering energies to action,
the beast-like dread of change when things are pretty well with
us; and the compensation for this animal pain is animal
rest. We must feel while we are working that the time will
come when we shall not have to work. Also the rest, when it
comes, must be long enough to allow us to enjoy it; it must be
longer than is merely necessary for us to recover the strength we
have expended in working, and it must be animal rest also in
this, that it must not be disturbed by anxiety, else we shall not
be able to enjoy it. If we have this amount and kind of
rest we shall, so far, be no worse off than the beasts.</p>
<p>As to the hope of product, I have said that Nature compels us
to work for that. It remains for <i>us</i> to look to it
that we <i>do</i> really produce something, and not nothing, or
at least nothing that we want or are allowed to use. If we
look to this and use our wills we shall, so far, be better than
machines.</p>
<p>The hope of pleasure in the work itself: how strange that hope
must seem to some of my readers—to most of them! Yet
I think that to all living things there is a pleasure in the
exercise of their energies, and that even beasts rejoice in being
lithe and swift and strong. But a man at work, making
something which he feels will exist because he is working at it
and wills it, is exercising the energies of his mind and soul as
well as of his body. Memory and imagination help him as he
works. Not only his own thoughts, but the thoughts of the
men of past ages guide his hands; and, as a part of the human
race, he creates. If we work thus we shall be men, and our
days will be happy and eventful.</p>
<p>Thus worthy work carries with it the hope of pleasure in rest,
the hope of the pleasure in our using what it makes, and the hope
of pleasure in our daily creative skill.</p>
<p>All other work but this is worthless; it is slaves’
work—mere toiling to live, that we may live to toil.</p>
<p>Therefore, since we have, as it were, a pair of scales in
which to weigh the work now done in the world, let us use
them. Let us estimate the worthiness of the work we do,
after so many thousand years of toil, so many promises of hope
deferred, such boundless exultation over the progress of
civilization and the gain of liberty.</p>
<p>Now, the first thing as to the work done in civilization and
the easiest to notice is that it is portioned out very unequally
amongst the different classes of society. First, there are
people—not a few—who do no work, and make no pretence
of doing any. Next, there are people, and very many of
them, who work fairly hard, though with abundant easements and
holidays, claimed and allowed; and lastly, there are people who
work so hard that they may be said to do nothing else than work,
and are accordingly called “the working classes,” as
distinguished from the middle classes and the rich, or
aristocracy, whom I have mentioned above.</p>
<p>It is clear that this inequality presses heavily upon the
“working” class, and must visibly tend to destroy
their hope of rest at least, and so, in that particular, make
them worse off than mere beasts of the field; but that is not the
sum and end of our folly of turning useful work into useless
toil, but only the beginning of it.</p>
<p>For first, as to the class of rich people doing no work, we
all know that they consume a great deal while they produce
nothing. Therefore, clearly, they have to be kept at the
expense of those who do work, just as paupers have, and are a
mere burden on the community. In these days there are many
who have learned to see this, though they can see no further into
the evils of our present system, and have formed no idea of any
scheme for getting rid of this burden; though perhaps they have a
vague hope that changes in the system of voting for members of
the House of Commons may, as if by magic, tend in that
direction. With such hopes or superstitions we need not
trouble ourselves. Moreover, this class, the aristocracy,
once thought most necessary to the State, is scant of numbers,
and has now no power of its own, but depends on the support of
the class next below it—the middle class. In fact, it
is really composed either of the most successful men of that
class, or of their immediate descendants.</p>
<p>As to the middle class, including the trading, manufacturing,
and professional people of our society, they do, as a rule, seem
to work quite hard enough, and so at first sight might be thought
to help the community, and not burden it. But by far the
greater part of them, though they work, do not produce, and even
when they do produce, as in the case of those engaged (wastefully
indeed) in the distribution of goods, or doctors, or (genuine)
artists and literary men, they consume out of all proportion to
their due share. The commercial and manufacturing part of
them, the most powerful part, spend their lives and energies in
fighting amongst themselves for their respective shares of the
wealth which they <i>force</i> the genuine workers to provide for
them; the others are almost wholly the hangers-on of these; they
do not work for the public, but a privileged class: they are the
parasites of property, sometimes, as in the case of lawyers,
undisguisedly so; sometimes, as the doctors and others above
mentioned, professing to be useful, but too often of no use save
as supporters of the system of folly, fraud, and tyranny of which
they form a part. And all these we must remember have, as a
rule, one aim in view; not the production of utilities, but the
gaining of a position either for themselves or their children in
which they will not have to work at all. It is their
ambition and the end of their whole lives to gain, if not for
themselves yet at least for their children, the proud position of
being obvious burdens on the community. For their work
itself in spite of the sham dignity with which they surround it,
they care nothing: save a few enthusiasts, men of science, art or
letters, who, if they are not the salt of the earth, are at least
(and oh, the pity of it!) the salt of the miserable system of
which they are the slaves, which hinders and thwarts them at
every turn, and even sometimes corrupts them.</p>
<p>Here then is another class, this time very numerous and
all-powerful, which produces very little and consumes enormously,
and is therefore in the main supported, as paupers are, by the
real producers. The class that remains to be considered
produces all that is produced, and supports both itself and the
other classes, though it is placed in a position of inferiority
to them; real inferiority, mind you, involving a degradation both
of mind and body. But it is a necessary consequence of this
tyranny and folly that again many of these workers are not
producers. A vast number of them once more are merely
parasites of property, some of them openly so, as the soldiers by
land and sea who are kept on foot for the perpetuating of
national rivalries and enmities, and for the purposes of the
national struggle for the share of the product of unpaid
labour. But besides this obvious burden on the producers
and the scarcely less obvious one of domestic servants, there is
first the army of clerks, shop-assistants, and so forth, who are
engaged in the service of the private war for wealth, which, as
above said, is the real occupation of the well-to-do middle
class. This is a larger body of workers than might be
supposed, for it includes amongst others all those engaged in
what I should call competitive salesmanship, or, to use a less
dignified word, the puffery of wares, which has now got to such a
pitch that there are many things which cost far more to sell than
they do to make.</p>
<p>Next there is the mass of people employed in making all those
articles of folly and luxury, the demand for which is the outcome
of the existence of the rich non-producing classes; things which
people leading a manly and uncorrupted life would not ask for or
dream of. These things, whoever may gainsay me, I will for
ever refuse to call wealth: they are not wealth, but waste.
Wealth is what Nature gives us and what a reasonable man can make
out of the gifts of Nature for his reasonable use. The
sunlight, the fresh air, the unspoiled face of the earth, food,
raiment and housing necessary and decent; the storing up of
knowledge of all kinds, and the power of disseminating it; means
of free communication between man and man; works of art, the
beauty which man creates when he is most a man, most aspiring and
thoughtful—all things which serve the pleasure of people,
free, manly and uncorrupted. This is wealth. Nor can
I think of anything worth having which does not come under one or
other of these heads. But think, I beseech you, of the
product of England, the workshop of the world, and will you not
be bewildered, as I am, at the thought of the mass of things
which no sane man could desire, but which our useless toil
makes—and sells?</p>
<p>Now, further, there is even a sadder industry yet, which is
forced on many, very many, of our workers—the making of
wares which are necessary to them and their brethren, <i>because
they are an inferior class</i>. For if many men live
without producing, nay, must live lives so empty and foolish that
they <i>force</i> a great part of the workers to produce wares
which no one needs, not even the rich, it follows that most men
must be poor; and, living as they do on wages from those whom
they support, cannot get for their use the <i>goods</i> which men
naturally desire, but must put up with miserable makeshifts for
them, with coarse food that does not nourish, with rotten raiment
which does not shelter, with wretched houses which may well make
a town-dweller in civilization look back with regret to the tent
of the nomad tribe, or the cave of the pre-historic savage.
Nay, the workers must even lend a hand to the great industrial
invention of the age—adulteration, and by its help produce
for their own use shams and mockeries of the luxury of the rich;
for the wage-earners must always live as the wage-payers bid
them, and their very habits of life are <i>forced</i> on them by
their masters.</p>
<p>But it is waste of time to try to express in words due
contempt of the productions of the much-praised cheapness of our
epoch. It must be enough to say that this cheapness is
necessary to the system of exploiting on which modern manufacture
rests. In other words, our society includes a great mass of
slaves, who must be fed, clothed, housed and amused as slaves,
and that their daily necessity compels them to make the
slave-wares whose use is the perpetuation of their slavery.</p>
<p>To sum up, then, concerning the manner of work in civilized
States, these States are composed of three classes—a class
which does not even pretend to work, a class which pretends to
work but which produces nothing, and a class which works, but is
compelled by the other two classes to do work which is often
unproductive.</p>
<p>Civilization therefore wastes its own resources, and will do
so as long as the present system lasts. These are cold
words with which to describe the tyranny under which we suffer;
try then to consider what they mean.</p>
<p>There is a certain amount of natural material and of natural
forces in the world, and a certain amount of labour-power
inherent in the persons of the men that inhabit it. Men
urged by their necessities and desires have laboured for many
thousands of years at the task of subjugating the forces of
Nature and of making the natural material useful to them.
To our eyes, since we cannot see into the future, that struggle
with Nature seems nearly over, and the victory of the human race
over her nearly complete. And, looking backwards to the
time when history first began, we note that the progress of that
victory has been far swifter and more startling within the last
two hundred years than ever before. Surely, therefore, we
moderns ought to be in all ways vastly better off than any who
have gone before us. Surely we ought, one and all of us, to
be wealthy, to be well furnished with the good things which our
victory over Nature has won for us.</p>
<p>But what is the real fact? Who will dare to deny that
the great mass of civilized men are poor? So poor are they
that it is mere childishness troubling ourselves to discuss
whether perhaps they are in some ways a little better off than
their forefathers. They are poor; nor can their poverty be
measured by the poverty of a resourceless savage, for he knows of
nothing else than his poverty; that he should be cold, hungry,
houseless, dirty, ignorant, all that is to him as natural as that
he should have a skin. But for us, for the most of us,
civilization has bred desires which she forbids us to satisfy,
and so is not merely a niggard but a torturer also.</p>
<p>Thus then have the fruits of our victory over Nature been
stolen from us, thus has compulsion by Nature to labour in hope
of rest, gain, and pleasure been turned into compulsion by man to
labour in hope—of living to labour!</p>
<p>What shall we do then, can we mend it?</p>
<p>Well, remember once more that it is not our remote ancestors
who achieved the victory over Nature, but our fathers, nay, our
very selves. For us to sit hopeless and helpless then would
be a strange folly indeed: be sure that we can amend it.
What, then, is the first thing to be done?</p>
<p>We have seen that modern society is divided into two classes,
one of which is <i>privileged</i> to be kept by the labour of the
other—that is, it forces the other to work for it and takes
from this inferior class everything that it <i>can</i> take from
it, and uses the wealth so taken to keep its own members in a
superior position, to make them beings of a higher order than the
others: longer lived, more beautiful, more honoured, more refined
than those of the other class. I do not say that it
troubles itself about its members being positively long lived,
beautiful or refined, but merely insists that they shall be so
relatively to the inferior class. As also it cannot use the
labour-power of the inferior class fairly in producing real
wealth, it wastes it wholesale in the production of rubbish.</p>
<p>It is this robbery and waste on the part of the minority which
keeps the majority poor; if it could be shown that it is
necessary for the preservation of society that this should be
submitted to, little more could be said on the matter, save that
the despair of the oppressed majority would probably at some time
or other destroy Society. But it has been shown, on the
contrary, even by such incomplete experiments, for instance, as
Co-operation (so called), that the existence of a privileged
class is by no means necessary for the production of wealth, but
rather for the “government” of the producers of
wealth, or, in other words, for the upholding of privilege.</p>
<p>The first step to be taken then is to abolish a class of men
privileged to shirk their duties as men, thus forcing others to
do the work which they refuse to do. All must work
according to their ability, and so produce what they
consume—that is, each man should work as well as he can for
his own livelihood, and his livelihood should be assured to him;
that is to say, all the advantages which society would provide
for each and all of its members.</p>
<p>Thus, at last, would true Society be founded. It would
rest on equality of condition. No man would be tormented
for the benefit of another—nay, no one man would be
tormented for the benefit of Society. Nor, indeed, can that
order be called Society which is not upheld for the benefit of
every one of its members.</p>
<p>But since men live now, badly as they live, when so many
people do not produce at all, and when so much work is wasted, it
is clear that, under conditions where all produced and no work
was wasted, not only would every one work with the certain hope
of gaining a due share of wealth by his work, but also he could
not miss his due share of rest. Here, then, are two out of
the three kinds of hope mentioned above as an essential part of
worthy work assured to the worker. When class robbery is
abolished, every man will reap the fruits of his labour, every
man will have due rest—leisure, that is. Some
Socialists might say we need not go any further than this; it is
enough that the worker should get the full produce of his work,
and that his rest should be abundant. But though the
compulsion of man’s tyranny is thus abolished, I yet demand
compensation for the compulsion of Nature’s
necessity. As long as the work is repulsive it will still
be a burden which must be taken up daily, and even so would mar
our life, even though the hours of labour were short. What
we want to do is to add to our wealth without diminishing our
pleasure. Nature will not be finally conquered till our
work becomes a part of the pleasure of our lives.</p>
<p>That first step of freeing people from the compulsion to
labour needlessly will at least put us on the way towards this
happy end; for we shall then have time and opportunities for
bringing it about. As things are now, between the waste of
labour-power in mere idleness and its waste in unproductive work,
it is clear that the world of civilization is supported by a
small part of its people; when all were working usefully for its
support, the share of work which each would have to do would be
but small, if our standard of life were about on the footing of
what well-to-do and refined people now think desirable. We
shall have labour-power to spare, and shall, in short, be as
wealthy as we please. It will be easy to live. If we
were to wake up some morning now, under our present system, and
find it “easy to live,” that system would force us to
set to work at once and make it hard to live; we should call that
“developing our resources,” or some such fine
name. The multiplication of labour has become a necessity
for us, and as long as that goes on no ingenuity in the invention
of machines will be of any real use to us. Each new machine
will cause a certain amount of misery among the workers whose
special industry it may disturb; so many of them will be reduced
from skilled to unskilled workmen, and then gradually matters
will slip into their due grooves, and all will work apparently
smoothly again; and if it were not that all this is preparing
revolution, things would be, for the greater part of men, just as
they were before the new wonderful invention.</p>
<p>But when revolution has made it “easy to live,”
when all are working harmoniously together and there is no one to
rob the worker of his time, that is to say, his life; in those
coming days there will be no compulsion on us to go on producing
things we do not want, no compulsion on us to labour for nothing;
we shall be able calmly and thoughtfully to consider what we
shall do with our wealth of labour-power. Now, for my part,
I think the first use we ought to make of that wealth, of that
freedom, should be to make all our labour, even the commonest and
most necessary, pleasant to everybody; for thinking over the
matter carefully I can see that the one course which will
certainly make life happy in the face of all accidents and
troubles is to take a pleasurable interest in all the details of
life. And lest perchance you think that an assertion too
universally accepted to be worth making, let me remind you how
entirely modern civilization forbids it; with what sordid, and
even terrible, details it surrounds the life of the poor, what a
mechanical and empty life she forces on the rich; and how rare a
holiday it is for any of us to feel ourselves a part of Nature,
and unhurriedly, thoughtfully, and happily to note the course of
our lives amidst all the little links of events which connect
them with the lives of others, and build up the great whole of
humanity.</p>
<p>But such a holiday our whole lives might be, if we were
resolute to make all our labour reasonable and pleasant.
But we must be resolute indeed; for no half measures will help us
here. It has been said already that our present joyless
labour, and our lives scared and anxious as the life of a hunted
beast, are forced upon us by the present system of producing for
the profit of the privileged classes. It is necessary to
state what this means. Under the present system of wages
and capital the “manufacturer” (most absurdly so
called, since a manufacturer means a person who makes with his
hands) having a monopoly of the means whereby the power to labour
inherent in every man’s body can be used for production, is
the master of those who are not so privileged; he, and he alone,
is able to make use of this labour-power, which, on the other
hand, is the only commodity by means of which his
“capital,” that is to say, the accumulated product of
past labour, can be made productive to him. He therefore
buys the labour-power of those who are bare of capital and can
only live by selling it to him; his purpose in this transaction
is to increase his capital, to make it breed. It is clear
that if he paid those with whom he makes his bargain the full
value of their labour, that is to say, all that they produced, he
would fail in his purpose. But since he is the monopolist
of the means of productive labour, he can <i>compel</i> them to
make a bargain better for him and worse for them than that; which
bargain is that after they have earned their livelihood,
estimated according to a standard high enough to ensure their
peaceable submission to his mastership, the rest (and by far the
larger part as a matter of fact) of what they produce shall
belong to him, shall be his <i>property</i> to do as he likes
with, to use or abuse at his pleasure; which property is, as we
all know, jealously guarded by army and navy, police and prison;
in short, by that huge mass of physical force which superstition,
habit, fear of death by starvation—<span class="smcap">Ignorance</span>, in one word, among the
propertyless masses enables the propertied classes to use for the
subjection of—their slaves.</p>
<p>Now, at other times, other evils resulting from this system
may be put forward. What I want to point out now is the
impossibility of our attaining to attractive labour under this
system, and to repeat that it is this robbery (there is no other
word for it) which wastes the available labour-power of the
civilized world, forcing many men to do nothing, and many, very
many more to do nothing useful; and forcing those who carry on
really useful labour to most burdensome over-work. For
understand once for all that the “manufacturer” aims
primarily at producing, by means of the labour he has stolen from
others, not goods but profits, that is, the “wealth”
that is produced over and above the livelihood of his workmen,
and the wear and tear of his machinery. Whether that
“wealth” is real or sham matters nothing to
him. If it sells and yields him a “profit” it
is all right. I have said that, owing to there being rich
people who have more money than they can spend reasonably, and
who therefore buy sham wealth, there is waste on that side; and
also that, owing to there being poor people who cannot afford to
buy things which are worth making, there is waste on that
side. So that the “demand” which the capitalist
“supplies” is a false demand. The market in
which he sells is “rigged” by the miserable
inequalities produced by the robbery of the system of Capital and
Wages.</p>
<p>It is this system, therefore, which we must be resolute in
getting rid of, if we are to attain to happy and useful work for
all. The first step towards making labour attractive is to
get the means of making labour fruitful, the Capital, including
the land, machinery, factories, &c., into the hands of the
community, to be used for the good of all alike, so that we might
all work at “supplying” the real
“demands” of each and all—that is to say, work
for livelihood, instead of working to supply the demand of the
profit market—instead of working for profit—i.e., the
power of compelling other men to work against their will.</p>
<p>When this first step has been taken and men begin to
understand that Nature wills all men either to work or starve,
and when they are no longer such fools as to allow some the
alternative of stealing, when this happy day is come, we shall
then be relieved from the tax of waste, and consequently shall
find that we have, as aforesaid, a mass of labour-power
available, which will enable us to live as we please within
reasonable limits. We shall no longer be hurried and driven
by the fear of starvation, which at present presses no less on
the greater part of men in civilized communities than it does on
mere savages. The first and most obvious necessities will
be so easily provided for in a community in which there is no
waste of labour, that we shall have time to look round and
consider what we really do want, that can be obtained without
over-taxing our energies; for the often-expressed fear of mere
idleness falling upon us when the force supplied by the present
hierarchy of compulsion is withdrawn, is a fear which is but
generated by the burden of excessive and repulsive labour, which
we most of us have to bear at present.</p>
<p>I say once more that, in my belief, the first thing which we
shall think so necessary as to be worth sacrificing some idle
time for, will be the attractiveness of labour. No very
heavy sacrifice will be required for attaining this object, but
some <i>will</i> be required. For we may hope that men who
have just waded through a period of strife and revolution will be
the last to put up long with a life of mere utilitarianism,
though Socialists are sometimes accused by ignorant persons of
aiming at such a life. On the other hand, the ornamental
part of modern life is already rotten to the core, and must be
utterly swept away before the new order of things is
realized. There is nothing of it—there is nothing
which could come of it that could satisfy the aspirations of men
set free from the tyranny of commercialism.</p>
<p>We must begin to build up the ornamental part of
life—its pleasures, bodily and mental, scientific and
artistic, social and individual—on the basis of work
undertaken willingly and cheerfully, with the consciousness of
benefiting ourselves and our neighbours by it. Such
absolutely necessary work as we should have to do would in the
first place take up but a small part of each day, and so far
would not be burdensome; but it would be a task of daily
recurrence, and therefore would spoil our day’s pleasure
unless it were made at least endurable while it lasted. In
other words, all labour, even the commonest, must be made
attractive.</p>
<p>How can this be done?—is the question the answer to
which will take up the rest of this paper. In giving some
hints on this question, I know that, while all Socialists will
agree with many of the suggestions made, some of them may seem to
some strange and venturesome. These must be considered as
being given without any intention of dogmatizing, and as merely
expressing my own personal opinion.</p>
<p>From all that has been said already it follows that labour, to
be attractive, must be directed towards some obviously useful
end, unless in cases where it is undertaken voluntarily by each
individual as a pastime. This element of obvious usefulness
is all the more to be counted on in sweetening tasks otherwise
irksome, since social morality, the responsibility of man towards
the life of man, will, in the new order of things, take the place
of theological morality, or the responsibility of man to some
abstract idea. Next, the day’s work will be
short. This need not be insisted on. It is clear that
with work unwasted it <i>can</i> be short. It is clear also
that much work which is now a torment, would be easily endurable
if it were much shortened.</p>
<p>Variety of work is the next point, and a most important
one. To compel a man to do day after day the same task,
without any hope of escape or change, means nothing short of
turning his life into a prison-torment. Nothing but the
tyranny of profit-grinding makes this necessary. A man
might easily learn and practise at least three crafts, varying
sedentary occupation with outdoor—occupation calling for
the exercise of strong bodily energy for work in which the mind
had more to do. There are few men, for instance, who would
not wish to spend part of their lives in the most necessary and
pleasantest of all work—cultivating the earth. One
thing which will make this variety of employment possible will be
the form that education will take in a socially ordered
community. At present all education is directed towards the
end of fitting people to take their places in the hierarchy of
commerce—these as masters, those as workmen. The
education of the masters is more ornamental than that of the
workmen, but it is commercial still; and even at the ancient
universities learning is but little regarded, unless it can in
the long run be made <i>to pay</i>. Due education is a
totally different thing from this, and concerns itself in finding
out what different people are fit for, and helping them along the
road which they are inclined to take. In a duly ordered
society, therefore, young people would be taught such handicrafts
as they had a turn for as a part of their education, the
discipline of their minds and bodies; and adults would also have
opportunities of learning in the same schools, for the
development of individual capacities would be of all things
chiefly aimed at by education, instead, as now, the subordination
of all capacities to the great end of “money-making”
for oneself—or one’s master. The amount of
talent, and even genius, which the present system crushes, and
which would be drawn out by such a system, would make our daily
work easy and interesting.</p>
<p>Under this head of variety I will note one product of industry
which has suffered so much from commercialism that it can
scarcely be said to exist, and is, indeed, so foreign from our
epoch that I fear there are some who will find it difficult to
understand what I have to say on the subject, which I
nevertheless must say, since it is really a most important
one. I mean that side of art which is, or ought to be, done
by the ordinary workman while he is about his ordinary work, and
which has got to be called, very properly, Popular Art.
This art, I repeat, no longer exists now, having been killed by
commercialism. But from the beginning of man’s
contest with Nature till the rise of the present capitalistic
system, it was alive, and generally flourished. While it
lasted, everything that was made by man was adorned by man, just
as everything made by Nature is adorned by her. The
craftsman, as he fashioned the thing he had under his hand,
ornamented it so naturally and so entirely without conscious
effort, that it is often difficult to distinguish where the mere
utilitarian part of his work ended and the ornamental
began. Now the origin of this art was the necessity that
the workman felt for variety in his work, and though the beauty
produced by this desire was a great gift to the world, yet the
obtaining variety and pleasure in the work by the workman was a
matter of more importance still, for it stamped all labour with
the impress of pleasure. All this has now quite disappeared
from the work of civilization. If you wish to have
ornament, you must pay specially for it, and the workman is
compelled to produce ornament, as he is to produce other
wares. He is compelled to pretend happiness in his work, so
that the beauty produced by man’s hand, which was once a
solace to his labour, has now become an extra burden to him, and
ornament is now but one of the follies of useless toil, and
perhaps not the least irksome of its fetters.</p>
<p>Besides the short duration of labour, its conscious
usefulness, and the variety which should go with it, there is
another thing needed to make it attractive, and that is pleasant
surroundings. The misery and squalor which we people of
civilization bear with so much complacency as a necessary part of
the manufacturing system, is just as necessary to the community
at large as a proportionate amount of filth would be in the house
of a private rich man. If such a man were to allow the
cinders to be raked all over his drawing-room, and a privy to be
established in each corner of his dining-room, if he habitually
made a dust and refuse heap of his once beautiful garden, never
washed his sheets or changed his tablecloth, and made his family
sleep five in a bed, he would surely find himself in the claws of
a commission <i>de lunatico</i>. But such acts of miserly
folly are just what our present society is doing daily under the
compulsion of a supposed necessity, which is nothing short of
madness. I beg you to bring your commission of lunacy
against civilization without more delay.</p>
<p>For all our crowded towns and bewildering factories are simply
the outcome of the profit system. Capitalistic manufacture,
capitalistic land-owning, and capitalistic exchange force men
into big cities in order to manipulate them in the interests of
capital; the same tyranny contracts the due space of the factory
so much that (for instance) the interior of a great weaving-shed
is almost as ridiculous a spectacle as it is a horrible
one. There is no other necessity for all this, save the
necessity for grinding profits out of men’s lives, and of
producing cheap goods for the use (and subjection) of the slaves
who grind. All labour is not yet driven into factories;
often where it is there is no necessity for it, save again the
profit-tyranny. People engaged in all such labour need by
no means be compelled to pig together in close city
quarters. There is no reason why they should not follow
their occupations in quiet country homes, in industrial colleges,
in small towns, or, in short, where they find it happiest for
them to live.</p>
<p>As to that part of labour which must be associated on a large
scale, this very factory system, under a reasonable order of
things (though to my mind there might still be drawbacks to it),
would at least offer opportunities for a full and eager social
life surrounded by many pleasures. The factories might be
centres of intellectual activity also, and work in them might
well be varied very much: the tending of the necessary machinery
might to each individual be but a short part of the day’s
work. The other work might vary from raising food from the
surrounding country to the study and practice of art and
science. It is a matter of course that people engaged in
such work, and being the masters of their own lives, would not
allow any hurry or want of foresight to force them into enduring
dirt, disorder, or want of room. Science duly applied would
enable them to get rid of refuse, to minimize, if not wholly to
destroy, all the inconveniences which at present attend the use
of elaborate machinery, such as smoke, stench and noise; nor
would they endure that the buildings in which they worked or
lived should be ugly blots on the fair face of the earth.
Beginning by making their factories, buildings, and sheds decent
and convenient like their homes, they would infallibly go on to
make them not merely negatively good, inoffensive merely, but
even beautiful, so that the glorious art of architecture, now for
some time slain by commercial greed, would be born again and
flourish.</p>
<p>So, you see, I claim that work in a duly ordered community
should be made attractive by the consciousness of usefulness, by
its being carried on with intelligent interest, by variety, and
by its being exercised amidst pleasurable surroundings. But
I have also claimed, as we all do, that the day’s work
should not be wearisomely long. It may be said, “How
can you make this last claim square with the others? If the
work is to be so refined, will not the goods made be very
expensive?”</p>
<p>I do admit, as I have said before, that some sacrifice will be
necessary in order to make labour attractive. I mean that,
if we <i>could</i> be contented in a free community to work in
the same hurried, dirty, disorderly, heartless way as we do now,
we might shorten our day’s labour very much more than I
suppose we shall do, taking all kinds of labour into
account. But if we did, it would mean that our new-won
freedom of condition would leave us listless and wretched, if not
anxious, as we are now, which I hold is simply impossible.
We should be contented to make the sacrifices necessary for
raising our condition to the standard called out for as desirable
by the whole community. Nor only so. We should,
individually, be emulous to sacrifice quite freely still more of
our time and our ease towards the raising of the standard of
life. Persons, either by themselves or associated for such
purposes, would freely, and for the love of the work and for its
results—stimulated by the hope of the pleasure of
creation—produce those ornaments of life for the service of
all, which they are now bribed to produce (or pretend to produce)
for the service of a few rich men. The experiment of a
civilized community living wholly without art or literature has
not yet been tried. The past degradation and corruption of
civilization may force this denial of pleasure upon the society
which will arise from its ashes. If that must be, we will
accept the passing phase of utilitarianism as a foundation for
the art which is to be. If the cripple and the starveling
disappear from our streets, if the earth nourish us all alike, if
the sun shine for all of us alike, if to one and all of us the
glorious drama of the earth—day and night, summer and
winter—can be presented as a thing to understand and love,
we can afford to wait awhile till we are purified from the shame
of the past corruption, and till art arises again amongst people
freed from the terror of the slave and the shame of the
robber.</p>
<p>Meantime, in any case, the refinement, thoughtfulness, and
deliberation of labour must indeed be paid for, but not by
compulsion to labour long hours. Our epoch has invented
machines which would have appeared wild dreams to the men of past
ages, and of those machines we have as yet <i>made no
use</i>.</p>
<p>They are called “labour-saving” machines—a
commonly used phrase which implies what we expect of them; but we
do not get what we expect. What they really do is to reduce
the skilled labourer to the ranks of the unskilled, to increase
the number of the “reserve army of labour”—that
is, to increase the precariousness of life among the workers and
to intensify the labour of those who serve the machines (as
slaves their masters). All this they do by the way, while
they pile up the profits of the employers of labour, or force
them to expend those profits in bitter commercial war with each
other. In a true society these miracles of ingenuity would
be for the first time used for minimizing the amount of time
spent in unattractive labour, which by their means might be so
reduced as to be but a very light burden on each
individual. All the more as these machines would most
certainly be very much improved when it was no longer a question
as to whether their improvement would “pay” the
individual, but rather whether it would benefit the
community.</p>
<p>So much for the ordinary use of machinery, which would
probably, after a time, be somewhat restricted when men found out
that there was no need for anxiety as to mere subsistence, and
learned to take an interest and pleasure in handiwork which, done
deliberately and thoughtfully, could be made more attractive than
machine work.</p>
<p>Again, as people freed from the daily terror of starvation
find out what they really wanted, being no longer compelled by
anything but their own needs, they would refuse to produce the
mere inanities which are now called luxuries, or the poison and
trash now called cheap wares. No one would make plush
breeches when there were no flunkies to wear them, nor would
anybody waste his time over making oleomargarine when no one was
<i>compelled</i> to abstain from real butter. Adulteration
laws are only needed in a society of thieves—and in such a
society they are a dead letter.</p>
<p>Socialists are often asked how work of the rougher and more
repulsive kind could be carried out in the new condition of
things. To attempt to answer such questions fully or
authoritatively would be attempting the impossibility of
constructing a scheme of a new society out of the materials of
the old, before we knew which of those materials would disappear
and which endure through the evolution which is leading us to the
great change. Yet it is not difficult to conceive of some
arrangement whereby those who did the roughest work should work
for the shortest spells. And again, what is said above of
the variety of work applies specially here. Once more I
say, that for a man to be the whole of his life hopelessly
engaged in performing one repulsive and never-ending task, is an
arrangement fit enough for the hell imagined by theologians, but
scarcely fit for any other form of society. Lastly, if this
rougher work were of any special kind, we may suppose that
special volunteers would be called on to perform it, who would
surely be forthcoming, unless men in a state of freedom should
lose the sparks of manliness which they possessed as slaves.</p>
<p>And yet if there be any work which cannot be made other than
repulsive, either by the shortness of its duration or the
intermittency of its recurrence, or by the sense of special and
peculiar usefulness (and therefore honour) in the mind of the man
who performs it freely,—if there be any work which cannot
be but a torment to the worker, what then? Well, then, let
us see if the heavens will fall on us if we leave it undone, for
it were better that they should. The produce of such work
cannot be worth the price of it.</p>
<p>Now we have seen that the semi-theological dogma that all
labour, under any circumstances, is a blessing to the labourer,
is hypocritical and false; that, on the other hand, labour is
good when due hope of rest and pleasure accompanies it. We
have weighed the work of civilization in the balance and found it
wanting, since hope is mostly lacking to it, and therefore we see
that civilization has bred a dire curse for men. But we
have seen also that the work of the world might be carried on in
hope and with pleasure if it were not wasted by folly and
tyranny, by the perpetual strife of opposing classes.</p>
<div class="gapspace"> </div>
<p>It is Peace, therefore, which we need in order that we may
live and work in hope and with pleasure. Peace so much
desired, if we may trust men’s words, but which has been so
continually and steadily rejected by them in deeds. But for
us, let us set our hearts on it and win it at whatever cost.</p>
<p>What the cost may be, who can tell? Will it be possible
to win peace peaceably? Alas, how can it be? We are
so hemmed in by wrong and folly, that in one way or other we must
always be fighting against them: our own lives may see no end to
the struggle, perhaps no obvious hope of the end. It may be
that the best we can hope to see is that struggle getting sharper
and bitterer day by day, until it breaks out openly at last into
the slaughter of men by actual warfare instead of by the slower
and crueller methods of “peaceful” commerce. If
we live to see that, we shall live to see much; for it will mean
the rich classes grown conscious of their own wrong and robbery,
and consciously defending them by open violence; and then the end
will be drawing near.</p>
<p>But in any case, and whatever the nature of our strife for
peace may be, if we only aim at it steadily and with singleness
of heart, and ever keep it in view, a reflection from that peace
of the future will illumine the turmoil and trouble of our lives,
whether the trouble be seemingly petty, or obviously tragic; and
we shall, in our hopes at least, live the lives of men: nor can
the present times give us any reward greater than that.</p>
<h2><SPAN name="page174"></SPAN><span class="pagenum"></span>DAWN OF A NEW EPOCH.</h2>
<p><span class="smcap">Perhaps</span> some of my readers may
think that the above title is not a correct one: it may be said,
a new epoch is always dawning, change is always going on, and it
goes on so gradually that we do not know when we are out of an
old epoch and into a new one. There is truth in that, at
least to this extent, that no age can see itself: we must stand
some way off before the confused picture with its rugged surface
can resolve itself into its due order, and seem to be something
with a definite purpose carried through all its details.
Nevertheless, when we look back on history we do distinguish
periods in the lapse of time that are not merely arbitrary ones,
we note the early growth of the ideas which are to form the new
order of things, we note their development into the transitional
period, and finally the new epoch is revealed to us bearing in
its full development, unseen as yet, the seeds of the newer order
still which shall transform it in its turn into something
else.</p>
<p>Moreover, there are periods in which even those alive in them
become more or less conscious of the change which is always going
on; the old ideas which were once so exciting to men’s
imaginations, now cease to move them, though they may be accepted
as dull and necessary platitudes: the material circumstances of
man’s life which were once only struggled with in detail,
and only according to a kind of law made manifest in their
working, are in such times conscious of change, and are only
accepted under protest until some means can be found to alter
them. The old and dying order, once silent and
all-powerful, tries to express itself violently, and becomes at
once noisy and weak. The nascent order once too weak to be
conscious of need of expression, or capable of it if it were,
becomes conscious now and finds a voice. The silent sap of
the years is being laid aside for open assault; the men are
gathering under arms in the trenches, and the forlorn hope is
ready, no longer trifling with little solacements of the time of
weary waiting, but looking forward to mere death or the joy of
victory.</p>
<p>Now I think, and some who read this will agree with me, that
we are now living in one of these times of conscious change; we
not only are, but we also feel ourselves to be living between the
old and the new; we are expecting something to happen, as the
phrase goes: at such times it behoves us to understand what is
the old which is dying, what is the new which is coming into
existence? That is a question practically important to us
all, since these periods of conscious change are also, in one way
or other, times of serious combat, and each of us, if he does not
look to it and learn to understand what is going on, may find
himself fighting on the wrong side, the side with which he really
does not sympathize.</p>
<p>What is the combat we are now entering upon—who is it to
be fought between? Absolutism and Democracy, perhaps some
will answer. Not quite, I think; that contest was
practically settled by the great French Revolution; it is only
its embers which are burning now: or at least that is so in the
countries which are not belated like Russia, for instance.
Democracy, or at least what used to be considered Democracy, is
now triumphant; and though it is true that there are countries
where freedom of speech is repressed besides Russia, as
<i>e.g.</i>, Germany and Ireland, <SPAN name="citation176"></SPAN><SPAN href="#footnote176" class="citation">[176]</SPAN> that only happens
when the rulers of the triumphant Democracy are beginning to be
afraid of the new order of things, now becoming conscious of
itself, and are being driven into reaction in consequence.
No, it is not Absolutism and Democracy as the French Revolution
understood those two words that are the enemies now: the issue is
deeper than it was; the two foes are now Mastership and
Fellowship. This is a far more serious quarrel than the old
one, and involves a much completer revolution. The grounds
of conflict are really quite different. Democracy said and
says, men shall not be the masters of others, because hereditary
privilege has made a race or a family so, and they happen to
belong to such race; they shall individually grow into being the
masters of others by the development of certain qualities under a
system of authority which <i>artificially</i> protects the wealth
of every man, if he has acquired it in accordance with this
artificial system, from the interference of every other, or from
all others combined.</p>
<p>The new order of things says, on the contrary, why have
masters at all? let us be <i>fellows</i> working in the harmony
of association for the common good, that is, for the greatest
happiness and completest development of every human being in the
community.</p>
<p>This ideal and hope of a new society founded on industrial
peace and forethought, bearing with it its own ethics, aiming at
a new and higher life for all men, has received the general name
of Socialism, and it is my firm belief that it is destined to
supersede the old order of things founded on industrial war, and
to be the next step in the progress of humanity.</p>
<p>Now, since I must explain further what are the aims of
Socialism, the ideal of the new epoch, I find that I must begin
by explaining to you what is the constitution of the old order
which it is destined to supplant. If I can make that clear
to you, I shall have also made clear to you the first aim of
Socialism: for I have said that the present and decaying order of
things, like those which have gone before it, has to be propped
up by a system of artificial authority; when that artificial
authority has been swept away, harmonious association will be
felt by all men to be a necessity of their happy and undegraded
existence on the earth, and Socialism will become the condition
under which we shall all live, and it will develop naturally, and
probably with no violent conflict, whatever detailed system may
be necessary: I say the struggle will not be over these details,
which will surely vary according to the difference of
unchangeable natural surroundings, but over the question, shall
it be mastership or fellowship?</p>
<p>Let us see then what is the condition of society under the
last development of mastership, the commercial system, which has
taken the place of the Feudal system.</p>
<p>Like all other systems of society, it is founded on the
necessity of man conquering his subsistence from Nature by
labour, and also, like most other systems that we know of, it
presupposes the unequal distribution of labour among different
classes of society, and the unequal distribution of the results
of that labour: it does not differ in that respect from the
system which it supplanted; it has only altered the method
whereby that unequal distribution should be arranged. There
are still rich people and poor people amongst us, as there were
in the Middle Ages; nay, there is no doubt that, relatively at
least to the sum of wealth existing, the rich are richer and the
poor are poorer now than they were then. However that may
be, in any case now as then there are people who have much work
and little wealth living beside other people who have much wealth
and little work. The richest are still the idlest, and
those who work hardest and perform the most painful tasks are the
worst rewarded for their labour.</p>
<p>To me, and I should hope to my readers, this seems grossly
unfair; and I may remind you here that the world has always had a
sense of its injustice. For century after century, while
society has strenuously bolstered up this injustice forcibly and
artificially, it has professed belief in philosophies, codes of
ethics, and religions which have inculcated justice and fair
dealing between men: nay, some of them have gone so far as to bid
us bear one another’s burdens, and have put before men the
duty, and in the long run the pleasure, of the strong working for
the weak, the wise for the foolish, the helpful for the helpless;
and yet these precepts of morality have been set aside in
practice as persistently as they have been preached in theory;
and naturally so, since they attack the very basis of class
society. I as a Socialist am bound to preach them to you
once more, assuring you that they are no mere foolish dreams
bidding us to do what we now must acknowledge to be impossible,
but reasonable rules of action, good for our defence against the
tyranny of Nature. Anyhow, honest men have the choice
before them of either putting these theories in practice or
rejecting them altogether. If they will but face that
dilemma, I think we shall soon have a new world of it; yet I fear
they will find it hard to do so: the theory is old, and we have
got used to it and its form of words: the practice is new, and
would involve responsibilities we have not yet thought much
of.</p>
<p>Now the great difference between our present system and that
of the feudal period is that, as far as the conditions of life
are concerned, all distinction of classes is abolished except
that between rich and poor: society is thus simplified; the
arbitrary distinction is gone, the real one remains and is far
more stringent than the arbitrary one was. Once all society
was rude, there was little real difference between the gentleman
and the non-gentleman, and you had to dress them differently from
one another in order to distinguish them. But now a
well-to-do man is a refined and cultivated being, enjoying to the
full his share of the conquest over Nature which the modern world
has achieved, while the poor man is rude and degraded, and has no
share in the wealth conquered by modern science from Nature: he
is certainly no better as to material condition than the serf of
the Middle Ages, perhaps he is worse: to my mind he is at least
worse than the savage living in a good climate.</p>
<p>I do not think that any thoughtful man seriously denies this:
let us try to see what brings it about; let us see it as clearly
as we all see that the hereditary privilege of the noble caste,
and the consequent serf slavery of the workers of the Middle
Ages, brought about the peculiar conditions of that period.</p>
<p>Society is now divided between two classes, those who
monopolize all the means of the production of wealth save one;
and those who possess nothing except that one, the Power of
Labour. That power of labour is useless to its possessors,
and cannot be exercised without the help of the other means of
production; but those who have nothing but
labour-power—i.e., who have no means of making others work
for them, must work for themselves in order to live; and they
must therefore apply to the owners of the means of fructifying
labour—i.e., the land, machinery, &c., for leave to
work that they may live. The possessing class (as for short
we will call them) are quite prepared to grant this leave, and
indeed they must grant it if they are to use the labour-power of
the non-possessing class for their own advantage, which is their
special privilege. But that privilege enables them to
<i>compel</i> the non-possessing class to sell them their
labour-power on terms which ensure the continuance of their
monopoly. These terms are at the outset very simple.
The possessing class, or masters, allow the men just so much of
the wealth produced by their labour as will give them such a
livelihood as is considered necessary at the time, and will
permit them to breed and rear children to a working age: that is
the simple condition of the “bargain” which obtains
when the labour-power required is low in quality, what is called
unskilled labour, and when the workers are too weak or ignorant
to combine so as to threaten the masters with some form of
rebellion. When skilled labour is wanted, and the labourer
has consequently cost more to produce, and is rarer to be found,
the price of the article is higher: as also when the commodity
labour takes to thinking and remembers that after all it is also
men, and as aforesaid holds out threats to the masters; in that
case they for their part generally think it prudent to give way,
when the competition of the market allows them to do so, and so
the standard of livelihood for the workers rises.</p>
<p>But to speak plainly, the greater part of the workers, in
spite of strikes and Trades’ Unions, do get little more
than a bare subsistence wage, and when they grow sick or old they
would die outright if it were not for the refuge afforded them by
the workhouse, which is purposely made as prison-like and
wretched as possible, in order to prevent the lower-paid workers
from taking refuge in it before the time of their
<i>industrial</i> death.</p>
<p>Now comes the question as to how the masters are able to force
the men to sell their commodity labour-power so dirt-cheap
without treating them as the ancients treated their
slaves—i.e., with the whip. Well, of course you
understand that the master having paid his workmen what they can
live upon, and having paid for the wear and tear of machinery and
other expenses of that kind, has for his share whatever remains
over and above, <i>the whole of which he gets from the exercise
of the labour-power possessed by the worker</i>: he is anxious
therefore to make the most of this privilege, and competes with
his fellow-manufacturers to the utmost in the market: so that the
distribution of wares is organized on a gambling basis, and as a
consequence many more hands are needed when trade is brisk than
when it is slack, or even in an ordinary condition: under the
stimulus also of the lust for acquiring this surplus value of
labour, the great machines of our epoch were invented and are
yearly improved, and they act on labour in a threefold way: first
they get rid of many hands; next they lower the quality of the
labour required, so that skilled work is wanted less and less;
thirdly, the improvement in them forces the workers to work
harder while they are at work, as notably in the cotton-spinning
industry. Also in most trades women and children are
employed, to whom it is not even pretended that a subsistence
wage is given. Owing to all these causes, the reserve army
of labour necessary to our present system of manufactures for the
gambling market, the introduction of labour-saving machines
(labour saved for the master, mind you, not the man), and the
intensifying of the labour while it lasts, the employment of the
auxiliary labour of women and children: owing to all this there
are in ordinary years even, not merely in specially bad years
like the current one, <SPAN name="citation184"></SPAN><SPAN href="#footnote184" class="citation">[184]</SPAN> more workers than
there is work for them to do. The workers therefore
undersell one another in disposing of their one commodity,
labour-power, and are forced to do so, or they would not be
allowed to work, and therefore would have to starve or go to the
prison called the workhouse. This is why the masters at the
present day are able to dispense with the exercise of obvious
violence which in bygone times they used towards their
slaves.</p>
<p>This then is the first distinction between the two great
classes of modern Society: the upper class possesses wealth, the
lower lacks wealth; but there is another distinction to which I
will now draw your attention: the class which lacks wealth is the
class that produces it, the class that possesses it does not
produce it, it consumes it only. If by any chance the
so-called lower class were to perish or leave the community,
production of wealth would come to a standstill, until the
wealth-owners had learned how to produce, until they had
descended from their position, and had taken the place of their
former slaves. If on the contrary, the wealth-owners were
to disappear, production of wealth would at the worst be only
hindered for awhile, and probably would go on pretty much as it
does now.</p>
<p>But you may say, though it is certain that some of the
wealth-owners, as landlords, holders of funds, and the like do
nothing, yet there are many of them who work hard. Well,
that is true, and perhaps nothing so clearly shows the extreme
folly of the present system than this fact that there are so many
able and industrious men employed by it, in working hard
at—nothing: nothing or worse. They work, but they do
not produce.</p>
<p>It is true that some useful occupations are in the hands of
the privileged classes, physic, education, and the fine arts,
<i>e.g.</i> The men who work at these occupations are
certainly working usefully; and all that we can say against them
is that they are sometimes paid too high in proportion to the pay
of other useful persons, which high pay is given them in
recognition of their being the parasites of the possessing
classes. But even as to numbers these are not a very large
part of the possessors of wealth, and, as to the wealth they
hold, it is quite insignificant compared with that held by those
who do nothing useful.</p>
<p>Of these last, some, as we all agree, do not pretend to do
anything except amuse themselves, and probably these are the
least harmful of the useless classes. Then there are others
who follow occupations which would have no place in a reasonable
condition of society, as, e.g., lawyers, judges, jailers, and
soldiers of the higher grades, and most Government
officials. Finally comes the much greater group of those
who are engaged in gambling or fighting for their individual
shares of the tribute which their class compels the working-class
to yield to it: these are the group that one calls broadly
business men, the conductors of our commerce, if you please to
call them so.</p>
<p>To extract a good proportion of this tribute, and to keep as
much as possible of it when extracted for oneself, is the main
business of life for these men, that is, for most well-to-do and
rich people; it is called, quite inaccurately,
“money-making;” and those who are most successful in
this occupation are, in spite of all hypocritical pretences to
the contrary, the persons most respected by the public.</p>
<p>A word or two as to the tribute extracted from the workers as
aforesaid. It is no trifle, but amounts to at least
two-thirds of all that the worker produces; but you must
understand that it is not all taken directly from the workman by
his immediate employer, but by the employing class. Besides
the tribute or profit of the direct employer, which is in all
cases as much as he can get amidst his competition or war with
other employers, the worker has also to pay taxes in various
forms, and the greater part of the wealth so extorted is at the
best merely wasted: and remember, whoever <i>seems</i> to pay the
taxes, labour in the long run is the only real taxpayer.
Then he has to pay house-rent, and very much heavier rent in
proportion to his earnings than well-to-do people have. He
has also to pay the commission of the middle-men who distribute
the goods which he has made, in a way so wasteful that now all
thinking people cry out against it, though they are quite
helpless against it in our present society. Finally, he has
often to pay an extra tax in the shape of a contribution to a
benefit society or trades’ union, which is really a tax on
the precariousness of his employment caused by the gambling of
his masters in the market. In short, besides the profit or
the result of unpaid labour which he yields to his immediate
master he has to give back a large part of his wages to the class
of which his master is a part.</p>
<p>The privilege of the possessing class therefore consists in
their living on this tribute, they themselves either not working
or working unproductively—i.e., living on the labour of
others; no otherwise than as the master of ancient days lived on
the labour of his slave, or as the baron lived on the labour of
his serf. If the capital of the rich man consists of land,
he is able to force a tenant to improve his land for him and pay
him tribute in the form of rack-rent; and at the end of the
transaction has his land again, generally improved, so that he
can begin again and go on for ever, he and his heirs, doing
nothing, a mere burden on the community for ever, while others
are working for him. If he has houses on his land he has
rent for them also, often receiving the value of the building
many times over, and in the end house and land once more.
Not seldom a piece of barren ground or swamp, worth nothing in
itself, becomes a source of huge fortune to him from the
development of a town or a district, and he pockets the results
of the labour of thousands upon thousands of men, and calls it
his property: or the earth beneath the surface is found to be
rich in coal or minerals, and again he must be paid vast sums for
allowing others to labour them into marketable wares, to which
labour he contributes nothing.</p>
<p>Or again, if his capital consists of cash, he goes into the
labour market and buys the labour-power of men, women and
children, and uses it for the production of wares which shall
bring him in a profit, buying it of course at the lowest price
that he can, availing himself of their necessities to keep their
livelihood down to the lowest point which they will bear: which
indeed he <i>must</i> do, or he himself will be overcome in the
war with his fellow-capitalists. Neither in this case does
he do any useful work, and he need not do any semblance of it,
since he may buy the brain-power of managers at a somewhat higher
rate than he buys the hand-power of the ordinary workman.
But even when he does seem to be doing something, and receives
the pompous title of “organizer of labour,” he is not
really organizing <i>labour</i>, but the battle with his
immediate enemies, the other capitalists, who are in the same
line of business with himself.</p>
<p>Furthermore, though it is true, as I have said, that the
working-class are the only producers, yet only a part of them are
allowed to produce usefully; for the men of the non-producing
classes having often much more wealth than they can <i>use</i>
are forced to <i>waste</i> it in mere luxuries and follies, that
on the one hand harm themselves, and on the other withdraw a very
large part of the workers from useful work, thereby compelling
those who do produce usefully to work the harder and more
grievously: in short, the essential accompaniment of the system
is waste.</p>
<p>How could it be otherwise, since it is a system of war?
I have mentioned incidentally that all the employers of labour
are at war with each other, and you will probably see that,
according to my account of the relations between the two great
classes, they also are at war. Each can only gain at the
others’ loss: the employing class is forced to make the
most of its privilege, the possession of the means for the
exercise of labour, and whatever it gets to itself can only be
got at the expense of the working-class; and that class in its
turn can only raise its standard of livelihood at the expense of
the possessing class; it is <i>forced</i> to yield as little
tribute to it as it can help; there is therefore constant war
always going on between these two classes, whether they are
conscious of it or not.</p>
<p>To recapitulate: In our modern society there are two classes,
a useful and a useless class; the useless class is called the
upper, the useful the lower class. The useless or upper
class, having the monopoly of all the means of the production of
wealth save the power of labour, can and does compel the useful
or lower class to work for its own disadvantage, and for the
advantage of the upper class; nor will the latter allow the
useful class to work on any other terms. This arrangement
necessarily means an increasing contest, first of the classes one
against the other, and next of the individuals of each class
among themselves.</p>
<p>Most thinking people admit the truth of what I have just
stated, but many of them believe that the system, though
obviously unjust and wasteful, is necessary (though perhaps they
cannot give their reasons for their belief), and so they can see
nothing for it but palliating the worst evils of the system: but,
since the various palliatives in fashion at one time or another
have failed each in its turn, I call upon them, firstly, to
consider whether the system itself might not be changed, and
secondly, to look round and note the signs of approaching
change.</p>
<p>Let us remember first that even savages live, though they have
poor tools, no machinery, and no co-operation, in their work: but
as soon as a man begins to use good tools and work with some kind
of co-operation he becomes able to produce more than enough for
his own bare necessaries, All industrial society is founded on
that fact, even from the time when workmen were mere chattel
slaves. What a strange society then is this of ours,
wherein while one set of people cannot use their wealth, they
have so much, but are obliged to waste it, another set are
scarcely if at all better than those hapless savages who have
neither tools nor co-operation! Surely if this cannot be
set right, civilized mankind must write itself down a civilized
fool.</p>
<p>Here is the workman now, thoroughly organized for production,
working for production with complete co-operation, and through
marvellous machines; surely if a slave in Aristotle’s time
could do more than keep himself alive, the present workman can do
much more—as we all very well know that he can. Why
therefore should he be otherwise than in a comfortable
condition? Simply because of the class system, which with
one hand plunders, and with the other wastes the wealth won by
the workman’s labour. If the workman had the full
results of his labour he would in all cases be comfortably off,
if he were working in an unwasteful way. But in order to
work unwastefully he must work for his own livelihood, and not to
enable another man to live without producing: if he has to
sustain another man in idleness who is capable of working for
himself, he is treated unfairly; and, believe me, he will only do
so as long he is compelled to submit by ignorance and brute
force. Well, then, he has a right to claim the wealth
produced by his labour, and in consequence to insist that all
shall produce who are able to do so; but also undoubtedly his
labour must be organized, or he will soon find himself relapsing
into the condition of the savage. But in order that his
labour may be organized properly he must have only one enemy to
contend with—Nature to wit, who as it were eggs him on to
the conflict against herself, and is grateful to him for
overcoming her; a friend in the guise of an enemy. There
must be no contention of man with man, but <i>association</i>
instead; so only can labour be really organized, harmoniously
organized. But harmony cannot co-exist with contention for
individual gain: men must work for the common gain if the world
is to be raised out of its present misery; therefore that claim
of the workman (that is of every able man) must be subject to the
fact that he is but a part of a harmonious whole: he is worthless
without the co-operation of his fellows, who help him according
to their capacities: he ought to feel, and will feel when he has
his right senses, that he is working for his own interest when he
is working for that of the community.</p>
<p>So working, his work must always be profitable, therefore no
obstacle must be thrown in the way of his work: the means whereby
his labour-power can be exercised must be free to him. The
privilege of the proprietary class must come to an end.
Remember that at present the custom is that a person so
privileged is in the position of a man (with a policeman or so to
help) guarding the gate of a field which will supply livelihood
to whomsoever can work in it: crowds of people who don’t
want to die come to that gate; but there stands law and order,
and says “pay me five shillings before you go in;”
and he or she that hasn’t the five shillings has to stay
outside, and die—or live in the workhouse. Well, that
must be done away with; the field must be free to everybody that
can use it. To throw aside even this transparent metaphor,
those means of the fructification of labour, the land, machinery,
capital, means of transit, &c., which are now monopolized by
those who cannot use them, but who abuse them to force unpaid
labour out of others, must be free to those who can use them;
that is to say, the workers properly organized for production;
but you must remember that this will wrong no man, because as all
will do some service to the community—i.e., as there will
be no non-producing class, the organized workers will be the
whole community, there will be no one left out.</p>
<p>Society will thus be recast, and labour will be free from all
compulsion except the compulsion of Nature, which gives us
nothing for nothing. It would be futile to attempt to give
you details of the way in which this would be carried out; since
the very essence of it is freedom and the abolition of all
arbitrary or artificial authority; but I will ask you to
understand one thing: you will no doubt want to know what is to
become of private property under such a system, which at first
sight would not seem to forbid the accumulation of wealth, and
along with that accumulation the formation of new classes of rich
and poor.</p>
<p>Now private property as at present understood implies the
holding of wealth by an individual as against all others, whether
the holder can use it or not: he may, and not seldom he does,
accumulate capital, or the stored-up labour of past generations,
and neither use it himself nor allow others to use it: he may,
and often he does, engross the first necessity of labour, land,
and neither use it himself or allow any one else to use it; and
though it is clear that in each case he is injuring the
community, the law is sternly on his side. In any case a
rich man accumulates property, not for his own use, but in order
that he may evade with impunity the law of Nature which bids man
labour for his livelihood, and also that he may enable his
children to do the same, that he and they may belong to the upper
or useless class: it is not wealth that he accumulates,
well-being, well-doing, bodily and mental; he soon comes to the
end of his real needs in that respect, even when they are most
exacting: it is power over others, what our forefathers called
<i>riches</i>, that he collects; power (as we have seen) to force
other people to live for his advantage poorer lives than they
should live. Understand that that <i>must</i> be the result
of the possession of <i>riches</i>.</p>
<p>Now this power to compel others to live poorly Socialism would
abolish entirely, and in that sense would make an end of private
property: nor would it need to make laws to prevent accumulation
artificially when once people had found out that they could
employ themselves, and that thereby every man could enjoy the
results of his own labour: for Socialism bases the rights of the
individual to possess wealth on his being able to use that wealth
for his own personal needs, and, labour being properly organized,
every person, male or female, not in nonage or otherwise
incapacitated from working, would have full opportunity to
produce wealth and thereby to satisfy his own personal needs; if
those needs went in any direction beyond those of an average man,
he would have to make personal sacrifices in order to satisfy
them; he would have, for instance, to work longer hours, or to
forego some luxury that he did not care for in order to obtain
something which he very much desired: so doing he would at the
worst injure no one: and you will clearly see that there is no
other choice for him between so doing and his forcing some one
else to forego <i>his</i> special desires; and this latter
proceeding by the way, when it is done without the sanction of
the most powerful part of society, is called <i>theft</i>; though
on the big scale and duly sanctioned by artificial laws, it is,
as we have seen, the groundwork of our present system. Once
more, that system refuses permission to people to produce unless
under artificial restrictions; under Socialism, every one who
could produce would be free to produce, so that the price of an
article would be just the cost of its production, and what we now
call profit would no longer exist: thus, for instance, if a
person wanted chairs, he would accumulate them till he had as
many as he could use, and then he would stop, since he would not
have been able to buy them for less than their cost of production
and could not sell them for more: in other words, they would be
nothing else than chairs; under the present system they may be
means of compulsion and destruction as formidable as loaded
rifles.</p>
<p>No one therefore would dispute with a man the possession of
what he had acquired without injury to others, and what he could
use without injuring them, and it would so remove temptations
toward the abuse of possession, that probably no laws would be
necessary to prevent it.</p>
<p>A few words now as to the differentiation of reward of labour,
as I know my readers are sure to want an exposition of the
Socialist views here as to those who direct labour or who have
specially excellent faculties towards production. And,
first, I will look on the super-excellent workman as an article
presumably needed by the community; and then say that, as with
other articles so with this, the community must pay the cost of
his production: for instance, it will have to seek him out, to
develop his special capacities, and satisfy any needs he may have
(if any) beyond those of an average man, so long as the
satisfaction of those needs is not hurtful to the community.</p>
<p>Furthermore, you cannot give him more than he can use so he
will not ask for more, and will not take it: it is true that his
work may be more special than another’s, but it is not more
necessary if you have organized labour properly; the ploughman
and the fisherman are as necessary to society as the scientist or
the artist, I will not say more necessary: neither is the
difficulty of producing the more special and excellent work at
all proportionate to its speciality or excellence: the higher
workman produces his work as easily perhaps as the lower does his
work; if he does not do so, you must give him extra leisure,
extra means for supplying the waste of power in him, but you can
give him nothing more. The only reward that you <i>can</i>
give the excellent workman is opportunity for developing and
exercising his excellent capacity. I repeat, you <i>can</i>
give him nothing more worth his having: all other rewards are
either illusory or harmful. I must say in passing, that our
present system of dealing with what is called a man of genius is
utterly absurd: we cruelly starve him and repress his capacity
when he is young; we foolishly pamper and flatter him and again
repress his capacity when he is middle-aged or old: we get the
least out of him, not the most.</p>
<p>These last words concern mere rarities in the way of workmen;
but in this respect it is only a matter of degree; the point of
the whole thing is this, that the director of labour is in his
place because he is fit for it, not by a mere accident; being fit
for it, he does it easier than he would do other work, and needs
no more compensation for the wear and tear of life than another
man does, and not needing it will not claim it, since it would be
no use to him; his special reward for his special labour is, I
repeat, that he can do it easily, and so does not feel it a
burden; nay, since he can do it <i>well</i> he likes doing it,
since indeed the main pleasure of life is the exercise of energy
in the development of our special capacities. Again, as
regards the workmen who are under his direction, he needs no
special dignity or authority; they know well enough that so long
as he fulfils his function and really does direct them, if they
do not heed him it will be at the cost of their labour being more
irksome and harder. All this, in short, is what is meant by
the organization of labour, which is, in other words, finding out
what work such and such people are fittest for and leaving them
free to do that: we won’t take the trouble to do that now,
with the result that people’s best faculties are wasted,
and that work is a heavy burden to them, which they naturally
shirk as much as they can; it should be rather a pleasure to
them: and I say straight out that, unless we find some means to
make all work more or less pleasurable, we shall never escape
from the great tyranny of the modern world.</p>
<p>Having mentioned the difference between the competitive and
commercial ideas on the subject of the individual holding of
wealth and the relative position of different groups of workmen,
I will very briefly say something on what for want of a better
word I must call the political position which we take up, or at
least what we look forward to in the long run. The
substitution of association for competition is the foundation of
Socialism, and will run through all acts done under it, and this
must act as between nations as well as between individuals: when
profits can no more be made, there will be no necessity for
holding together masses of men to draw together the greatest
proportion of profit to their locality, or to the real or
imaginary union of persons and corporations which is now called a
nation. What we now call a nation is a body whose function
it is to assert the special welfare of its incorporated members
at the expense of all other similar bodies: the death of
competition will deprive it of this function; since there will be
no attack there need be no defence, and it seems to me that this
function being taken away from the nation it can have no other,
and therefore must cease to exist as a political entity. On
this side of the movement opinion is growing steadily. It
is clear that, quite apart from Socialism, the idea of local
administration is pushing out that of centralized government: to
take a remarkable case: in the French Revolution of 1793, the
most advanced party was centralizing: in the latest French
revolution, that of the Commune of 1871, it was federalist.
Or take Ireland, the success which is to-day attending the
struggles of Ireland for independence is, I am quite sure, owing
to the spread of this idea: it no longer seems a monstrous
proposition to liberal-minded Englishmen that a country should
administer its own affairs: the feeling that it is not only just,
but also very convenient to all parties for it to do so, is
extinguishing the prejudices fostered by centuries of oppressive
and wasteful mastership. And I believe that Ireland will
show that her claim for self-government is not made on behalf of
national rivalry, but rather on behalf of genuine independence;
the consideration, on the one hand, of the needs of her own
population, and, on the other, goodwill towards that of other
localities. Well, the spread of this idea will make our
political work as Socialists the easier; men will at last come to
see that the only way to avoid the tyranny and waste of
bureaucracy is by the Federation of Independent Communities:
their federation being for definite purposes: for furthering the
organization of labour, by ascertaining the real demand for
commodities, and so avoiding waste: for organizing the
distribution of goods, the migration of persons—in short,
the friendly intercommunication of people whose interests are
common, although the circumstances of their natural surroundings
made necessary differences of life and manners between them.</p>
<p>I have thus sketched something of the outline of Socialism, by
showing that its aim is first to get rid of the monopoly of the
means of fructifying labour, so that labour may be free to all,
and its resulting wealth may not be engrossed by a few, and so
cause the misery and degradation of the many: and, secondly, that
it aims at organizing labour so that none of it may be wasted,
using as a means thereto the free development of each man’s
capacity; and, thirdly, that it aims at getting rid of national
rivalry, which in point of fact means a condition of perpetual
war, sometimes of the money-bag, sometimes of the bullet, and
substituting for this worn-out superstition a system of free
communities living in harmonious federation with each other,
managing their own affairs by the free consent of their members;
yet acknowledging some kind of centre whose function it would be
to protect the principle whose practice the communities should
carry out; till at last those principles would be recognized by
every one always and intuitively, when the last vestiges of
centralization would die out.</p>
<p>I am well aware that this complete Socialism, which is
sometimes called Communism, cannot be realized all at once;
society will be changed from its basis when we make the form of
robbery called profit impossible by giving labour full and free
access to the means of its fructification—i.e., to raw
material. The demand for this emancipation of labour is the
basis on which all Socialists may unite. On more indefinite
grounds they cannot meet other groups of politicians; they can
only rejoice at seeing the ground cleared of controversies which
are really dead, in order that the last controversy may be
settled that we can at present foresee, and the question solved
as to whether or no it is necessary, as some people think it is,
that society should be composed of two groups of dishonest
persons, slaves submitting to be slaves, yet for ever trying to
cheat their masters, and masters conscious of their having no
support for their dishonesty of eating the common stock without
adding to it save the mere organization of brute force, which
they have to assert for ever in all details of life against the
natural desire of man to be free.</p>
<p>It may be hoped that we of this generation may be able to
prove that it is unnecessary; but it will, doubt it not, take
many generations yet to prove that it is necessary for such
degradation to last as long as humanity does; and when that is
finally proved we shall at least have one hope left—that
humanity will not last long.</p>
<h2>FOOTNOTES.</h2>
<p><SPAN name="footnote13"></SPAN><SPAN href="#citation13" class="footnote">[13]</SPAN> Falsely; because the privileged
classes have at their back the force of the Executive by means of
which to compel the unprivileged to accept their terms; if this
is “free competition” there is no meaning in
words.</p>
<p><SPAN name="footnote37a"></SPAN><SPAN href="#citation37a" class="footnote">[37a]</SPAN> Read at the Conference convened
by the Fabian Society at South Place Institute, June 11,
1886.</p>
<p><SPAN name="footnote37b"></SPAN><SPAN href="#citation37b" class="footnote">[37b]</SPAN> They <i>have</i> been
“rather rough,” you may say, and have done more than
merely hold their sentimental position. Well, I still say
(February 1888) that the present open tyranny which sends
political opponents to prison, both in England and Ireland, and
breaks Radical heads in the street for attempting to attend
political meetings, is not Tory, but Whig; not the old Tory
“divine right of kings,” but the new Tory,
<i>i.e.</i>, Tory-tinted Whig, “divine right of
property” made Bloody Sunday possible. I admit that I
did not expect in 1886 that we should in 1887 and 1888 be having
such a brilliant example of the tyranny of a parliamentary
majority; in fact, I did not reckon on the force of the
impenetrable stupidity of the Prigs in alliance with the Whigs
marching under the rather ragged banner of sham Toryism.</p>
<p><SPAN name="footnote43"></SPAN><SPAN href="#citation43" class="footnote">[43]</SPAN> As true now (February 1888) as
then: the murder of the Chicago Anarchists, to wit.</p>
<p><SPAN name="footnote87"></SPAN><SPAN href="#citation87" class="footnote">[87]</SPAN> I suppose he was speaking of the
frame houses of Kent.</p>
<p><SPAN name="footnote176"></SPAN><SPAN href="#citation176" class="footnote">[176]</SPAN> And the brick and mortar country
London, also, it seems (Feb. 1888).</p>
<p><SPAN name="footnote184"></SPAN><SPAN href="#citation184" class="footnote">[184]</SPAN> 1886, to wit.</p>
<SPAN name="endofbook"></SPAN>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />